John Locke on Property
Clifford Cobb and Fred Foldvary
[1999]
Fred Foldvary:
Locke's logic becomes perverted by bringing in money; he seems to be
troubled by the logical implication of his proviso (perhaps because
the landed interests would be offended and cause him trouble?) and
sought an escape through the twisted logic regarding money. It doesn't
work. Now the population has way more than doubled, and even at the
time of Locke, land of equal quality was no longer available in
cities, for example. Locke is silent on the implementation of his
proviso. Maybe he was afraid of the power of the big landowners. At
any rate, the geoist/Georgist interpretation is fully consistent with
Locke's proviso, and the only one that really confronts it. We can
reject Locke's backtracking related to money as logically unsound and
contradictory to his sound logic regarding the proviso.
Cliff Cobb:
It seems to me that Locke's logic is not perverted by the
introduction of money. He says that if people can appropriate only
that amount of land that they themselves can work (i.e., as farmers,
because he does not consider commercial land), then no one would be
able to appropriate an excessive amount. However, the existence of
money (and the ability to exchange land for money) permits some the
capacity to achieve an unlimited accumulation of assets, including
land.
Yet, even in the absence of money and even if we assume that land has
value only for farming (which seems to be Locke's implicit
assumption), his proviso is still self-contradictory on its own terms.
Everyone might receive 10-30 acres of farmland, depending on soil
quality to meet his "enough and as good" terms, but 10 miles
outside of London or Liverpool and 100 miles west of Boston were
hardly equivalent in value. It would appear that he did not understand
the concept of rent, and more particularly that the margin is created
by location more than by soil quality.
If we take away the assumption that is valuable only for farming, the
proviso's terms are even more implausible. I presume that by 1680, a
small lot in central London was already worth hundreds of times what a
small farm was worth in the countryside. If that is the case, the only
way (as Fred suggests above) of solving the problem of "enough
and as good" is through the monetization of the value of land,
which is then distributed equally among all citizens. What Locke saw
as a problem (money) was actually part of the solution.
Part 2
Cliff here with some ideas about Locke that completely turn upside
down the usual reading of him. In fact, the ideas below cast doubt (in
my mind at least) on the use of Locke as the basis of any
geo-libertarian thinking. I had always wondered (and still do) how
Locke was situated in relation to the English Civil War and the
Restoration. The discussion below offers some insights into that
question, but only a beginning.
Some months ago, I raised a concern that those who rely on the
Lockean analysis of property rights never seem to mention the rest of
Locke's writings, specifically his Essay on Human Understanding. Not
having read the latter myself (other than a few paragraphs), I did not
have any particular problem in mind. It simply seemed that one should
consider someone's philosophy as a whole, not just one particular
outcropping of it.
In the last few days, I was reading Staughton Lynd, Intellectual
Origins of American Radicalism. In the introduction, he shows how most
American radicals, including Henry George, have made based their
radical prescription on the "truths self-evident" in the
Declaration of Independence (human equality and natural rights).
In Chapter 1, Lynd points out that by the 1760s, sophisticated
thinkers "viewed with amused contempt" arguments based on
the state of nature, the social contract, and the natural rights of
man. These had come to be viewed as human inventions, not conditions
of nature. The Declaration of Independence appeared "from the
standpoint of the ethical relativism of a Montesquieu, Voltaire, or
Hume [to be] a piece of provincial propaganda. . . unworthy of serious
intellectual attention."
According to Lynd (who draws from Carl Becker's books, The
Declaration of Independence and The Heavenly City of the
Eighteenth-Century Philosophers), there was an intellectual crisis in
the 18th century over the question of natural rights. The problem lay
in the language of "self-evident" truths, which were derived
from a law of nature that Locke had said in his Second Treatise was "writ
in the hearts of mankind" and which "cease not" in
society. Yet, Locke himself, in his Essay on Human Understanding had
argued against intuitive knowledge. Locke's epistemology was purely
environmental or based on sense experience. There was a fundamental
contradiction between rights known through intuition and a theory of
perception that precluded any knowledge of such rights. There can be
no enduring "self-evident" truths if truth is found only in
the passing moments of sense experience. Thus, rights to life,
liberty, and property could not be grounded in Nature or knowledge of
God, if ideas of right and wrong are entirely dependent on particular
contexts.
As a result of this internal contradiction within Locke's thought, "English
political philosophy in the eighteenth century turned away form
natural rights toward a social science characterized by ethical
relativism and pragmatic accommodation to existing reality."
Thus, Locke's epistemology lent support to conservatives who proposed
that people needed to accommodate themselves to the existing order
rather than resist it. Apparently, even Locke's popularizers, John
Trenchard and Thomas Gordon (joint authors Cato's Letters from 1720 to
1723), were also convinced that "a Commonwealth," or
fundamental change in the social order, was a "Phantome"
that would "never appear again but in disordered Brains."
At this point, Lynd suggests that the conflict was more apparent than
real, since Locke himself was no radical. "Locke, who blamed
poverty on the poor, sought to protect all forms of property including
chattel slavery, and took it for granted that government must be the
business of educated gentlemen, would have been horrified to find his
doctrine turned toward the advocacy of common sense, government by
common men, finally even common property." Citing Locke's Letter
Concerning Toleration, Lynd says, "Locke systematically
segregated things sacred from things secular, allowing freedom of
conscience to religion only after carefully barring it from all
interference in secular society." (If this is a correct reading
of Locke, then it is quite similar to Martin Luther's view of the
relationship between individual conscience and civil law.)
Lynd points out that the chapter on property in the Locke's Second
Treatise "begins with the observation that God has given the
earth to 'mankind in common' and ends by rationalizing the unlimited
accumulation of wealth." (Lynd's point is that Locke invokes
traditional, Biblical ideas and images of morality in paragraph 25 in
order to build a case for a world of unlimited private accumulation in
paragraphs 46-50.) I will come back to this in a moment, but Lynd's
next step is interesting. He shows how the logic of the Second
Treatise is subsumed under the logic of Locke's epistemology. In the
absence of a human ability to know universal truths through intuition
or to understand the life experience of others, there can be no common
conception of the good life. Each individual becomes an island,
psychologically and morally speaking. Thus, the relationships between
people are not governed by shared experience. Interactions occur only
at the surface, among strangers. Locke: "No particular man can
know the existence of any other being, but only when, by actually
operating upon him, it makes itself perceived by him." Thus,
there is a certain logic in seeing private property, the extension of
the self that is publicly observable, as the sole basis for regulating
social interaction and defining the principles of government.
Lynd shows that Thomas Paine and the English Dissenters with whom he
and Ben Franklin associated overcame the problem of grounding natural
rights by going back to writers before Locke: "John Lilburne,
Gerrard Winstanley, Richard Overton, and other religious republicans
of the 1640s and 1650s." As Lynd argues, "the ascendancy of
Dissenting radicalism represented a return to an essentially religious
outlook. . . . For them the greate secular truths were 'self-evident'
in the same sense as the truth of religion, which is to say
intuitively accessible to the average man." Thus, the Dissenters
openly criticized Locke's epistemology in order to offer an
alternative theory of rights. They proposed an intuitionist
epistemology, whereby truth could be perceived through intuition, not
the senses. In particular, Richard Price did this in A Review of the
Principal Questions and Difficulties in Morals in 1758. (One of the
reasons Locke repudiated intuitionism {and the concept of religious
knowledge independent of the senses} was his fear of the reassertion
of Papal authority in England. He wanted there to be no basis for
those who spoke in the name of religion to interfere with civil
authority.) [I would just note, in defense of Locke's concern, that
grounding of authority in an "inner light" as the activists
of the Radical Reformation did, offers no method of determining which
"inner light" is correct when there are conflicting views of
God's design. This, in turn, gives way to pure power politics.]
Rather than continue in this vein, I want to return briefly to Lynd's
claim that Locke "ends by rationalizing the unlimited
accumulation of wealth" in paragraphs 46-50 of the Second
Treatise. Reading those paragraphs again, I now see what role the
introduction of money plays for Locke. At the end of paragraph 46,
Locke says that a person exceeds the legitimate bounds of private
ownership "not lying in the largeness of his Possession, but the
perishing of any thing uselessly in it." The point he has been
making is that it is unethical for someone to take land from the
commons if doing so causes waste--as in someone growing more acorns
and apples than he or she can eat. "He was only to look that he
used them [acorns and apples] before they spoiled; else he took more
than his share, and robb'd others." The solution to this problem
of spoilage was the introduction of money. This allowed someone to own
great tracts of land which would generate far more produce than an
individual or family could possibly consume. By trading this produce
for a metal [gold or silver] that did not spoil, however, the owner
could be said legitimately to have a claim on that property. In
paragraph 50, the jaws of the trap fall shut: "it is plain that
Men have agreed to disproportionate and unequal Possession of the
Earth, they having by a tacit and voluntary consent found out a way,
how a man may fairly possess more land than he himself can use the
product of, by receiving in exchange for the overplus, Gold and
Silver, which may be hoarded up without injury to any one, these
metals not spoiling or decaying in the hands of the possessor."
I'm not convinced that Lynd's interpretation of Locke is completely
correct. I am convinced, however, that Locke can be read as both
radical and as conservative, and that trying to determine which is the
"true" Locke may not be possible. I suspect it may be
necessary to learn more about Locke's social situation (his own
landownership for example and his relationship to the political
questions of his day) to interpret his writings correctly.
This may seem like an excessive concern with Locke. However, if his
writings are indeed one of the definitive starting points of classical
liberalism, the ambiguity in his writings may help explain some of the
puzzling contradictions (to me) in libertarian thought today.
Part 3
I continue to be troubled by Locke's analysis of property. Since I
began reading secondary sources (the first being Peter Laslett's
introduction to his critical edition of Two Treatises), it has become
more and more evident that Locke's treatment of property is, for him,
but a stepping stone to explain why government was instituted to solve
problems in a state of nature. To read his "proviso" out of
that context is to misread it. This is important because I now think
that Locke is saying exactly the opposite of what geo-libertarians
claim he is saying. I believe Locke's position is more in keeping with
the alodialists or royal libertarians than has previously been
proposed on this list.
Before turning to Locke, I want to make a comparison with Henry
George. In Progress and Poverty, Book VI, Chapter 2, George says: "We
must therefore substitute for the individual ownership of land a
common ownership." A few sentences later: "We must make
land common property." It is my understanding that certain
socialists in England, upon reading that, got off the train and
decided that they could support that proposition. In Great Britain's
constitutional crisis of 1909, when Parliament had to be dissolved
because the House of Lords would not sign a Budget Act that included
national rent collection (at a very low level, mind you), part of
Prime Minister Lloyd George's support came from socialists who saw
the collection of ground rent as a stepping stone toward public
ownership of all land in Great Britain. If one willfully chose to
ignore what George said in Book VIII, Chapter 2 ("I do not
propose either to purchase or to confiscate private property in
land." and "It is not necessary to conflscate land; it is
only necessary to confiscate rent."), one could contend that he
supported the socialist position of collectivization.
What I want to propose here is that reading Locke's "enough
and as good proviso" as Locke's position on private property in
land involves as much willful disregard of Locke's fuller purpose as
a reading of George as a proponent of collectivization.
The problem that Locke addresses in Two Treatises is how to
respond to Sir Robert Filmer who held 1) that citizens have an
absolute duty to obey the sovereign in the same way that a son has
an absolute duty to obey his father (the patriarchal thesis) and 2)
that the world was given to humans by God as common property and
that pure communism is the condition in the state of nature
(communal rights thesis). (I'm not sure how natural communism fit
with Filmer's patriarchal argument about the authority of kings.
Presumably he regarded the king as the representative of all people.
Therefore a grant from God to all humans in common is a grant to the
king. According to this view, private property is not a natural
right, but a grant from the monarch, and could be reversed.)
In any case, Filmer believed some people are ordained by God as
superior beings to rule over others. That was the thesis that Locke
sought to refute.
The derivation of private property from natural law plays a
prominent role in the Second Treatise because it is a place-holder
for all individual rights vis-a-vis civil authority. Without a
natural right to property, the individual is a mere vassal, subject
to the absolute, partriarchal authority of the king.
Locke's problem is to show how one can derive the existence of
civil authority from a state of nature in which all people are born
equal (i.e., without the natural authority of patriarchy). His
well-known answer is that people create civil society or a social
compact to protect their property.
In section 25, Locke explains that he seeks to show how to
justify private ownership in a state of nature "of that which
God gave to Mankind in common." (In other words, if God gave it
to us in common, which was Filmer's argument, how can he justify
individual property ownership in the state of nature?) He wants to
show that private property logically precedes the social compact and
thus does not depend on mutual consent. (If private property only
exists by mutual consent, then it can be taken away by government,
and liberty is always at risk.)
To make his case, Locke argues in section 27 that property comes
from self-ownership and the application of labor. (Earlier natural
law theorists Grotius and Pufendorf had argued that private
ownership arises from mutual consent, not from self-ownership and
labor. However, Laslett points out that Richard Baxter in 1680
published an argument similar to Locke's: "Propriety is
naturally antecedent to Government, which doth not Give it, but
regulate it to the Common good. Every man is born with a propriety
in his own members.") He introduces the idea that people can
take from nature as long as there is "enough and as good"
for others.
In 28-31, the application of labor to create property is treated
exclusively in terms of usufruct: the appropriation of the fruits of
nature (such as acorns, apples, and the grass his horse eats). At
this point, labor simply involves taking something from the commons.
This describes a primeval economy of hunting and gathering.
In 31, he says this right of appropriation is limited by
spoilage. As long as people limited themselves to what they could
actually use and as long as the world was not heavily populated,
there were no quarrels because everyone could pick all the fruit and
catch all the game they wanted.
Then, suddenly in 32, Locke makes an important shift. With the
same logic of mixing labor and nature, he now justifies the
ownership of land, not just usufruct. We have shifted from
hunting-gathering to an agrarian society. In 33, he applies the same
limit to ownership that he applied to usufruct: as long as there is
"enough and as good." But in 33, he says: "Nor was
this appropriation . . . any prejudice to any other man." Note
the use of the past tense. In 35, this becomes clearer. Whereas it
is no longer possible to remove land from the commons in fully
populated England without prejudice to others, it had been possible
"in the beginning and first peopling of the great Common of the
World." In 36, he repeats this by speaking of "the first
Ages of the World, when Men were more in danger to be lost" in
the wilderness. He says it is still possible for someone to claim
land without prejudice to others by going to America or to Spain.
Section 36 is the second great turning point in the argument,
where he begins to justify the concentration of land holdings, far
beyond his "enough and as good," which applied only to the
misty past or empty continents in his day. In 36, he says in
reference to the immediately preceding discussion of free land in
America and Spain: "But be this as it will, which I lay no
stress on." In other words, the continuing availability of land
somewhere in the world which can satisfy his "enough and as
good" is not relevant to the argument he wants to make. He
turns instead to money and commerce--the world of 17th century
England in which there is great inequality of land ownership. "This
I boldly affirm, That the same Rule of Property, namely that every
Man should have as much as he could make use of, would hold still in
the World, without straitning [constraining] any body, since there
is Land enough in the World to suffice double the Inhabitants had
not the Invention of Money, and the tacit Agreement of Men to put a
value on it, introduced (by Consent) larger Possessions, and a Right
to them; which, how it was done, I shall, by and by, shew more at
large."
As C.B. McPherson, The Political Theory of Possessive
Individualism (p. 203), says in reference to this passage: "The
natural law rule, which by its specific terms limited the amount
anyone could appropriate so that everyone could have as much as he
could use, does *not* now hold. . . . The reason the rule does not
now hold is not that the land has run out. . . . The introduction of
money by tacit consent has removed the previous natural limitations
of rightful appropriation." McPherson also emphasizes the
passage in section 50, where Locke reaffirms that the introduction
of money has created rightful inequality of ownership of land, and
where Locke says: "This partage of things, in an inequality of
private possessions, men have made practicable out of the bounds of
Societie, and without compact, only by putting a value on gold and
silver and tacitly agreeing in the use of Money." The key point
is that money exists "out of the bounds of Societie and without
compact." Money and unequal access to land are, like the moral
capacity to enter into contracts, aspects of the state of nature,
not a consequence of civil society. (McPherson, p. 210: "Locke
can assume that neither money nor contracts owe their validity to
the state.") Since the purpose of civil society is to protect
the natural right to property, it would presumably be improper for
civil society to alter the distribution of land ownership.
McPherson (p. 213) continues: "It may be thought that Locke's
justification of larger possessions on these grounds . . . is
strictly inconsistent with his assertion that the right to
appropriate is limited to what leaves enough and as good for others.
That would be so if the original assertion was made absolutely. But
it was not. It was asserted as a consequence of a prior principle,
namely, the natural right of every man to get the means of
subsistence by his labour. . . . That right can be satisfied in
either of two ways. One way is to stipulate the original ['enough
and as good'] limitation . . ., and it is only in the context of
still plentiful land that Locke asserts the limitation." The
other way is "by stipulating or assuming an arrangement which
ensures that those without land can get a subsistence by their
labour."
Thus, it seems that for Locke, the state of nature has two
stages: the first, a stage prior to the introduction of money in
which there is land "enough and as good" for everyone, and
a second stage in which money has *rightfully* allowed some to own
more land than others. Unequal ownership of land is natural and
moral, according to Locke, since it does not deprive people of their
natural right to property because each person owns himself or
herself and can earn subsistence by selling his or her labor. Self-
ownership, not the right to "enough and as good" land as
others, is thus the basis of the rest of his political argument.
In summary: Locke's own analysis provides a flimsy foundation
upon which to build a Georgist platform. Classical liberalism, as
represented by Locke, justifies extremes of inequality in access to
natural opportunities.
If Locke had argued otherwise, he would not only have been a
political radical (which he was, by authorizing rebellion against
unlawful government), he would also have been an economic radical in
the Georgist sense (which he was not). He was a radical in his
repudiation of the traditional, feudal conception of property rights
being derived from royal authority. But he did not propose that
every person had an equal right to land.
Further Comments by Fred Foldvary
Cliff Cobb wrote:
It seems to me that Locke's logic is not perverted by the
introduction of money. He says that if people can appropriate only
that amount of land that they themselves can work (i.e., as farmers,
because he does not consider commercial land), then no one would be
able to appropriate an excessive amount. However, the existence of
money (and the ability to exchange land for money) permits some the
capacity to achieve an unlimited accumulation of assets, including
land.
Fred Foldvary responds:
But Locke is historically wrong. Huge landholdings of estates and
empires don't necessarily require money. When the Spaniards took the
Indian lands and established the latifundia, they used guns rather
than money.
Cliff Cobb wrote:
Yet, even in the absence of money and even if we assume that land
has value only for farming (which seems to be Locke's implicit
assumption), his proviso is still self-contradictory on its own
terms. Everyone might receive 10-30 acres of farmland, depending on
soil quality to meet his "enough and as good" terms, but
10 miles outside of London or Liverpool and 100 miles west of Boston
were hardly equivalent in value.
Fred Foldvary responds:
There is no contradiction in the proviso itself. The proviso just
implies that in that case there is not land of equal quality freely
available, hence thet one may *not* simply claim it, not without
compensating others.
Cliff Cobb wrote:
It would appear that he did not understand the concept of rent,
and more particularly that the margin is created by location more
than by soil quality.
Fred Foldvary responds:
He just did not apply the proviso to paying rent as compensation
for there not being equally good land available. Locke's economic
writings indicate a good understanding of rent.
See his pamphlet "Some Considerations of the Consequences of
the Lowering of Interest" (1691) and "Further
Considerations" (1695). Also Karent Vaughn's book "John
Locke: Economist and Social Scientist" and the Locke entry in
Mark Blaug's *Great Economists before Keynes*.
Locke knew about "all devouring rent" long before Henry
George.
|