The Democratic Imperative
PART TWO
Edward J. Dodson
[A Response by Joseph Bast, President, Heartland Institute. Joseph
Bast is the president of The Heartland Institute, a nonprofit and
nonpartisan research institute based in Palatine, Illinois. He is the
coauthor of several books, including
Eco-Sanity: A Common-Sense Guide to Environmentalism (1994).]
INTRODUCTION
I commend Mr. Dodson for producing an ambitious paper covering many
of the most controversial topics of the day. I most appreciated his
frequent calls for further research and more debate. If there were
simple answers to the problems that afflict western civilization in
the Twentieth Century, we would have found them by now. Such problems
persevere precisely because their solutions are difficult to find and
possibly complex.
I should warn the reader that I am not a "Georgist," at
least not as I have come to understand the term. I have read quite a
lot of Henry George and admire his insights and the rigor of his
analysis. Most economists today would agree with much of what Mr.
George wrote, even though many haven't read him, and those that have
are loath to admit it. I have yet to meet a practicing economist who
didn't think that taxing land values is superior, in many ways, to
taxing improvements in real estate, income, or other tax bases. How
far one can take this insight, however, is where most of us part
company with "Georgism."
I counted eight distinct topic areas covered by Mr. Dodson, starting
with ways to expand citizen participation in the government process
and ending with comments on credit and banking. In the comments that
follow, I address only two of his topics: the relationship between
government and business, and optimal tax policies. Had I attempted to
address more than this, my comments would have been longer than Mr.
Dodson's essay. As it is, I see they rival his in length.
Relationship Between Government and Business
Mr. Dodson asks us to ponder ". . . what sort of principles
ought to govern the activities of businesses, particularly those that
adopt the corporate form of ownership." He proposes that
government's role vis a vis business be as follows:
The function of government ought to be two-fold: (I) to protect
the health and safety of all citizens; and (ii) to prevent the
formation of monopolies, contrived shortages and/or price fixing among
producers.
I believe that Mr. Dodson, in making this statement, does not
intend to put forward a new fundamental theory of government, but is
describing only the tasks that government ought to perform concerning
businesses. In other places in his paper, Mr. Dodson seems to support
a government of limited powers, though with a few notable exceptions.
Be this as it may, his statement of government's functions seems to me
to be incorrect and open to mischief.
The first proposed function could be read to give government a
license to interfere with and regulate many aspects of our lives. In
the name of protecting our health and safety, government could ban the
manufacture and sale of foods containing too much fat, sugar, or salt.
It could ban automobiles that can travel faster than 55 miles per hour
(or even 15 miles per hour). It could require businesses to begin each
day with a mandatory program of calisthenics for employees.
Common sense says each of us, individually, is responsible for our
own health and safety. Most of what affects our health and safety is
directly under our own control: what we eat and how much, whether or
not we smoke and how often, whether we engage in risky activities such
as skydiving or downhill skiing, and so forth. Who better to judge the
costs and benefits than the person committing the act? Government is
too distant from our day-to-day living to be a reliable watchdog of
our health and safety.
Government does have responsibilities in the areas of health and
safety, but they are incidental to government's real function, which
is to protect us from the use of force and fraud by others. Government
protects us from imposed or invisible risks that might be beyond our
own ability to anticipate or avoid when it prosecutes false
advertising, and when it holds companies liable for injuries caused by
defective products, negligence, pollution of common resources, etc.
Mr. Dodson and I probably agree on the value of regulations
pertaining to these activities, but our disagreement is more than one
of semantics. It is not a function of government vis a vis businesses
to protect the health and safety of consumers and workers. Rather,
government should do only what is necessary to protect us from the use
of force and fraud by others. Protection of health and safety, when it
occurs, is only the consequence of government fulfilling that one true
function.
Monopolies and Price Fixing
The second function of government proposed by Mr. Dodson ignores the
fact that government itself historically has been the source of "monopolies,
contrived shortages and/or price fixing among producers." In his
classic essay, "Is Government the Source of Monopoly?" Yale
Brozen described how government policies created monopolies (actually
cartels) in trucking, aeronautics, steamships, railroads, taxicabs,
sugar production, textiles . . . well, you get the picture. And it was
government regulation of oil prices that created the so-called "energy
crisis" of the 1970s. When deregulation was enacted in the 1980s,
prices fell and waiting lines disappeared.
It is grim testimony of the pervasiveness of anti-business propaganda
that so many Americans believe business is becoming increasingly
concentrated and non-competitive over time. In fact, the trend in most
industries is the opposite. New technologies, the decline of
international trade barriers, and the simple expansion of the size of
markets have all contributed to a decentralization of the marketplace.
More opportunities exist for new products and new businesses than ever
before. As a result, we are witnessing a burst of entrepreneurship as
"plain folks" step in to fill new consumer needs or past
needs more efficiently.
As was the case with health and safety, government's duty with regard
to monopolies and instances of price fixing should be limited to
preventing the use of force and fraud. So long as consumers are not
forced to buy goods from a particular producer, and so long as force
is not used to prevent potential competitors from entering a market,
monopolies and cartels will always and everywhere be short-lived. The
best policy for government to pursue, then, is to remove regulatory
and tax barriers to business start-ups and allow competition to
flourish.
Public Goods and Services
So far I have suggested replacing Mr. Dodson's two functions of
government vis a vis businesses with the single fundamental task of
preventing the use of force and fraud. To this I would add a second
function that Mr. Dodson overlooks: In a small number of areas,
government performs a valuable function by providing goods or services
that the market, because of high transaction costs or free-rider
problems, will not produce or produces only at a much higher cost.
The theory of such "public goods" seems to be quite sound,
though it suffers an embarrassing lack of bona fide examples in the
real world. For example, most light houses, roads, parks, and even
urban sanitary systems and traffic lights were privately financed and
owned prior to the expansion of government power around the turn of
the century. Markets have been amazingly creative at solving problems
now deemed to be the exclusive province of government.
Nonetheless, it would be useful, following Mr. Dodson's lead, to
propose some principles concerning government's role in the area of
public goods. I propose four:
(a) Governments should attempt to turn public goods into private
goods by reducing transactions costs or using its police powers to
discourage free riders. For example, a local government might be well
positioned to help bring together neighborhood residents and
businesses to discuss and solve community problems such as parking,
parks, or mass transit, without creating a government entity with the
power to provide such amenities.
(b) Governments should provide only such goods as services as can be
used by or would benefit everyone in a community. In the absence of
such a rule, general tax revenues are used to finance projects
benefiting only special interest groups, leading other groups to lobby
for new projects that would benefit only them.
(c) Governments should provide but not necessarily produce public
goods and services. The actual production of a good or service can be
contracted out to private companies or nonprofit groups, with
government retaining the power to set standards and competitively bid
the contracts.
(d) All arrangements to provide public goods and services should have
sunset provisions as a way to return (or advance) to private provision
sometime in the future. The fact that public provision seems necessary
today is no guarantee that a new technology or organizational
innovation won't make privatization possible tomorrow. Without sunset
clauses, government agencies often attain a kind of institutional
immortality.
The reader may think that, since I disagree so thoroughly with Mr.
Dodson's premises, that I will also disagree with most of what he says
regarding the relationship between government and business.
Surprisingly, that is not the case.
Although Mr. Dodson finds much to criticize about the modern
corporation (some of it on target, some I think is exaggerated), he is
careful to limit his policy prescriptions to the voluntary adoption of
cooperative ownership models and ways to improve education systems and
job retraining programs. He concludes, and I agree, that "this
approach to more responsible corporate behavior is far more desirable
than relying on government to adopt intrusive, regulatory or social
legislation." Much as I like this conclusion, though, it seems to
follow more readily from my notions of the appropriate role of
government than from Mr. Dodson's.
How Should the State Raise Revenues?
Mr. Dodson does a fine job summarizing the Georgist approach to
taxation. Since "our birthright as human beings is the right of
equal access to the earth," it necessarily follows that "titles
to nature and forms of other licenses that restrict equal access
create unnatural forms of property, privileges that are inherently
monopolistic." "Justice," he goes on to write, "demands
that the individual compensate all others in society for the privilege
of monopolizing access," and therefore "taxation of property
or of income derived from the use of property" is justified.
Henry George himself might add that land has characteristics making
it unlike any other kind of property, such as finite supply, its
creation by God rather than man, and its permanence, making land an
unlikely candidate for private ownership. Mr. George also saw (and on
this most modern economists would agree) that land is easier to tax
than other things because it cannot be moved or hidden, and a tax on
land values would have less effect on incentives to work and invest
than taxes on income or production. Finally, anticipating such
contemporary economists as Ronald Coase and Armen Alchian, Mr. George
saw ownership of land as a "bundle" of rights that could be
broken up, separately assigned, sold or retained by the state, and
taxed.
Replacing the current tax system with a tax on land values, as Mr.
George proposed and Mr. Dodson implicitly endorses, may indeed create
the "enormous increase in production" that Mr. George wrote
about in Social Problems and elsewhere. But I have some reservations.
Georgism and Technological Change
Widely noted advances in technology make location increasingly
irrelevant to the process of wealth creation. What Alvin Toffler calls
the "second wave" -- the transition from a manufacturing to
a service economy -- was already occurring during Mr. George's time,
and it was reducing the significance of land and location relative to
labor and capital. Mr. Toffler says we are now in a "third wave"
when information technologies make land and even capital unimportant.
We read, for example, about "virtual companies" that exist
only as people connected by phone and computer modems, moving
information and money around the world electronically.
Are Georgists proposing to tax a factor of production that is no
longer a significant part of the economy's most profitable businesses?
If such a tax is imposed, its major impact would be felt on
occupations and industries that cannot "go virtual," such as
agriculture and private homes. The result would be not less income
inequality, as Mr. George had hoped, but more.
Attempting to tax land values in downtown business districts would
quickly push the newly mobile information managers out to the suburbs,
rural communities, or even to other countries where they can work just
as easily. The result would be more urban sprawl and more empty space
in business districts, once again just the opposite of Mr. George's
predictions.
As little as 18 months from now, according to Burton Pines of
National Empowerment Television, interactive television will be in a
majority of homes in America. It will dramatically push forward the
trend toward shopping, working, and being entertained at home. It will
revolutionize retailing as well as the information processes that are
now the core of our service economy. In this brave new world, where is
the relevance of land and location? Why should we tax these things
when they now have little to do with wealth, the creation of wealth,
or justice?
I don't know the answers to these questions. There may be, however,
an alternative interpretation of the relationship between Georgism and
technological change. Henry George said land values are the only just
source of revenues for the state. Land values associated with
manufacturing and wealth creation are about to fall thanks to "third
wave" technologies. But the "third wave" also creates
less need for government-provided goods and services. Mr. George, in
short, may have had his finger on the way to make government "wither
away": As government becomes less necessary, its only just source
of funding contracts. De facto defunding! The reason we have too much
government today, then, may be because we failed to heed Mr. George's
advice a hundred years ago!
What Does Taxing Land Leave Out?
A theory of just taxation that competes with the Georgist paradigm is
that taxes are the price paid for public services. In the U.S., local
property taxes most closely reflect this rule, being high in
communities wishing to purchase high-quality schools and parks or
public services, and lower when such amenities are not publicly
provided.
Should all communities be required to provide only such amenities as
can be supported by the income generated from local land values? Or
could that budget be supplemented by fees based on actual use of
public facilities or general assessments? It's easy to say "yes,
of course each community can do as it chooses." But such an
answer contradicts Henry George, who said "Any recognition of the
equal right to life and liberty which would deny the right to property
- the right of a man to his labor and to the full fruits of his labor
- would be a mockery." (Social Problems, p. 96, emphasis added.)
Mr. George thought he had a complete theory of just taxation: nothing
beyond taxation of land values is compatible with our rights to life
and liberty. Contemporary Georgists who seek to "mix and match"
the land tax with user fees are seeking to capture an element of
justice -- in this case, taxes are the price willingly paid for public
services -- that they perceive to be missing from Georgism. They may
be right, but this opens the door to alternative theories of just
taxation, including social contract theories ("people can vote to
tax themselves") and even Marxist puffery ("from each
according to his ability . . . . "). This, it seems to me, is
more than a mere quibble.
Progressive Income Taxation
Mr. Dodson and I apparently agree that Georgism comes up short of a
complete theory of justice taxation, since he supports progressive
income taxation as a way to raise public funds if revenues from a land
tax are insufficient. Mr. Dodson writes, the "ability to pay
ought to be given the highest consideration." Mr. Dodson doesn't
tell us why. Does he believe those who produce the most value in
society should be penalized to prevent others from emulating them,
lest we grow too fast? Or perhaps punitive taxation is necessary to
humble the lucky and the talented? How would this benefit society?
The prospect of trial lawyers and stockbrokers making millions of
dollars a year telecommuting from their homes and paying not one penny
in land taxes might also have occurred to Mr. Dodson. Certainly, the
income tax he proposes would prevent these greedy "virtual
entrepreneurs" from keeping "the full fruits" of their
labor.
I believe Mr. Dodson's concern, and his proposal, are ill-considered
and decidedly un-Georgist. Like Mr. George, I strenuously oppose
income taxation. I especially abhor graduated income taxation --
whereby persons of higher income not only pay more, but
disproportionately more, of their earnings to the state -- which is
based entirely on envy rather than justice. Graduated income taxes
have the most corrosive effects imaginable on productivity, social
mobility, and the efficiency of tax collection.
Mr. Dodson tries to excuse his proposal for a graduated income tax by
saying, "to be sure, there is confiscation associated with this
supplemental means of raising public revenue; however, the depth of
confiscation is moderate . . . ." Sir, rape is rape even if only
partial penetration is achieved.
Conclusion
What is the correct relationship between government and business, and
how ought government be financed? Political philosophers as far back
as Plato grappled with these issues. Isn't it extraordinary that the
same questions dominate the political scene today? Should the Justice
Department have prevented Microsoft from acquiring Intuit, Inc? Should
the federal income tax be replaced with a flat tax or a national sales
tax?
Georgists should be playing a high-profile role in these debates.
Henry George had a profound insight into how taxes on production and
income stifle economic growth and perpetuate inequality. He was an
eloquent defender not only of the right to equal access to land, but
of all the natural rights appearing in the great English liberal
tradition. Those rights always need strong voices raised in their
defense.
I have not kept pace with recent Georgist scholarship, so I do not
know if the concerns expressed above have been raised and resolved by
other writers. I look forward to talking with Mr. Dodson and others to
find the answers.
Return
to PART ONE
|