Review of the Book:
Public and Private Property
by John Z. White
Walter Fairchild
[Reprinted from Land and Freedom,
July-August, 1935]
In this timely and interesting book, Mr. White presents a legal
viewpoint of the effect of grants of land by the State to individual
owners. It is a common belief that because of deeds of land in "fee
simple" to individuals which extend back to the sovereignty it is
impossible for the State now to recover the value of the land without
doing violence to constitutional provisions protecting private rights.
The author makes clear the distinction between a contract and a grant
by the State. The Darmouth College case, the Charles River Bridge case
and other cases famous in history, are discussed in detail to show the
tendency of the courts to preserve to the State those sovereign rights
and powers without which democratic government is impossible.
Tenure of land is a public thing a delegation of a sovereign power.
Failure to guard the sovereign power expressed by land holding and to
permit the value of the land holding power to be privately
appropriated is a derogation of sovereignty and tends to destroy
democracy.
If an aristocratic society is desired nothing needs to be done. The
manor house theory of tenure of land is exemplified today in Franklin
D. Roosevelt who is to the "manor born." It is quite in
keeping with President Roosevelt's tradition to see nothing
incongruous in the large land values held by Vincent Astor. There is
nothing of the hyprocrite in the President in this respect nor
inconsistent with his warfare against those who grind the face of the
poor or take speculative profits without regard to the upkeep of the
nation at large. The ownership of the manor house and manor lands, to
Mr. Roosevelt, carries with it not only the duty of seeing to it that
all the manor people, tenants and workers, are fed and clothed but
also the consciousness that failure to meet this duty is destructive
of the manor family itself. So the Mitchells and the Wiggins who take
profits without responsibility are met with righteous Rooseveltian
indignation, whereas the landed families who give benevolent
consideration to the tenantry receive a complacent blessing.
Against such a benevolent aristocracy Mr. White shows the necessity
of preserving to the State its full sovereignty over land if democracy
is to endure.
Land cannot be owned. It can only be used.
A labor product can be owned outright in the sense that it can be
consumed. Eggs can be physically eaten up.
A land title is a franchise for use. Land cannot be consumed.
In this distinction lies the fundamental difference between a grant
of land and a bill of sale of goods.
The proposition that land grants and franchises are the same in legal
principle is sound law.
This being so, it follows that nothing more is granted than is
directly contained in the terms of the grant. A franchise grant is
strictly construed in favor of the sovereignty.
A grant of land made in 1735, for example, contains no contract that
conveys away values created in 193S. What is granted is contained
within the four corners of the document. Nothing is contained in any
deed ancient or modern that requires the community in 1935 to deliver
the beneficial use of a school house, a library, a paved street or
other public service upon the land without collecting the cost
therefor.
Chief Justice Marshall in 1810 in a Georgia land case held that a
grant by the State is a contract. In 1840, however, Justice Miller,
supported by Chief Justice Chase and Justice Field, dissented in
Washington University vs. Rouse (8 Wall. 443). He said:
"We do not believe that any legislative body,
sitting under a State constitution of the usual character, has a
right to sell, to give, or to bargain away forever the taxing power
of the State ... To hold that any one of the annual legislatures
can, by contract, deprive the State forever of the power of
taxation, is to hold that they can destroy the government which they
are appointed to serve, and that their action in that regard is
strictly lawful."
The tendency of the courts is in the direction of the sound doctrine
quoted. The power of the State to tax is paramount over private
rights. Private possession of land, necessary to preserve the fruits
of labor, does not of itself impair sovereignty. It is only when we
permit the profits arising from this exercise of sovereign power to
flow into private pockets that such impairment occurs.
Democracy may delegate its police power to a magistrate without
impairing its sovereignty but if it were held that the magistrate
acquired a vested right to his office and could administer the office
for his private gain it would be a derogation of sovereignty.
Franchises for the use of streets by utility companies are no longer
granted in perpetuity or for years without a valuation to be paid for
use.
The true legal concept of the tenure of land as a franchise for use
subject to valuation is growing in consciousness and is tending to
dispel the idea that the State having granted land is without power to
collect the value of the use.
This book is a strong plea for the recognition of those legal
principles which constitute the foundation of democratic government
and without democracy, cannot endure.
It is well worth a studious reading.
|