Pure and Applied Economics
Oscar B. Johannsen
[Reprinted from The Gargoyle, November, 1961]
Inasmuch as the principles of economics are based on deductive
reasoning, it would appear that possibly in the interest of arriving
at a greater understanding of the world of reality, economics might be
divided into two categories - pure economics and physical or applied
economics - much as modern mathematics is divided into two phases,
pure mathematics and physical or applied mathematics.
Pure mathematics does not deal with any particular subject matter of
reality and has nothing to say about such items of interest to men, as
space. The theorems which are derived are true and certain because
they are analytical and not empirical. This means that the truth of a
theorem is derived by logical deduction from certain so called
undefined terms, usually called primitives, and some axioms. These
axioms are more or less arbitrarily enunciated. The theorems are true
as related to these primitives and axioms because they are merely
explicit statements of what is implicit in the primitives and axioms.
To put it simply, the primitives and axioms contain hidden meanings.
These meanings (theorems)are uncovered by means of logic. The theorems
do not assert anything which is theoretically new as compared with the
axioms and primitives from which they are derived. They are said to be
psychologically new in that we did not realize they were implicitly
contained in the initial assumptions.
Whether a theorem is factually correct in the world of reality is a
problem of empirical science, that is, it is a problem of applied
mathematics. Man can never be absolutely certain about empirical
results as the discovery of new facts may alter the results. However,
if all the evidence confirms the applied theorems, then they are
accepted "until further notice". This is all summarized in a
famous statement of Albert Einstein who said, "As far as the laws
of mathematics refer to reality they are not certain; and as far as
they are certain they do not refer to reality".
Inasmuch as in economics we are dealing with logical deductions from
fundamental definitions and axioms, could not the same approach be
taken? Can we construct a pure economics which would be certain as
long as it does not refer to reality, but as far as it does relate to
reality is not certain?
This writer believes it could be done, although it might be a rather
arid approach.
Such concepts, as man, land, labor, wealth, etc., which are our
initial terms, might be the primitives or undefined terms. In
mathematics such primitives are terms as line or point. (However,
while they are undefined, nonetheless, conceptually man does give them
the definitions which we usually visualize them to be,) There is no
question of the "truth or falsity of these terms, any more than
there is about the terms in a game of chess. In Chess, the primitives
might be the pieces, as the King, Queen, etc. The axioms would be the
rules of the game which were arbitrarily set up thousands of years
ago. The theorems would be the possible moves which could be made, and
are all implicit in the rules. these would be discovered by the
players by applying their deductive reasoning to the rules. The
discovery of these moves (or theorems) would not be theoretically new
as they are all implicit in the rules. However, as it has been
estimated that the possible moves in chess are in the order of
billions, it is obvious that no one could possibly discover all of
them no matter how many lifetimes he lived.
What value would it be to divide economics into pure and applied
parts? It might prove as valuable as it has in mathematics. Knowledge
was advanced. Originally mathematics started as physical math, as men
were interested in making physical measurements of areas. From these
considerations, mathematics in the abstract evolved. And this pure
mathematics proved invaluable to man. For example, Einstein as he
pondered his theory of relativity, looked for some mathematics that he
could use to deal with his concepts of space. He found it in Riemann's
geometry. This non-Euclidian geometry had been developed by Riemann
with no concern for any relationship which it might have with reality,
and yet, when Einstein needed a tool, there it was at hand, and with
tremendous practical value.
If man will try to do this in the field of economics, probably many
of the disputes among economists will disappear. The disputes usually
apply to the physical application of the theoretical laws. Today,
these "pure" economic relationships are not carefully
systemized, as the "pure" mathematical ones are. If they
were, then it could be shown that they are true in the abstract, and
there could be little or no dispute about them. As one of the great
problems in economics is that no two economists use the terms in the
same way or have quite the same understanding of the fundamental
axioms or assumptions, there is little meeting of the minds. Should we
not at least give this method a trial?
|