Aesthetics as a Factor in Social Reform
Alexander MacKendrick
[Reprinted from the Single Tax Review,
March-April 1916]
The part that may be played by the Aesthetic sense in the evolution
of sweeter manners and nobler laws, and of public morals generally,
has probably never been adequately appreciated by our
society-reconstructors and social reformers. It has indeed been
recognized by poets and others that the sensitiveness to the ideals of
the Good, the True, and the Beautiful act and react upon one another.
Some have even affirmed their identity and maintained the
impossibility of conceiving one member of the Trinity in isolation
from the other two. Such recognition, however, of the relation between
the three constituent elements in human virtue has for the most part
been confined to those thinkers who stand apart from the rough work of
the social uplifter, and who live on a plane of thought above that of
ordinary mortals. In a general way it may be affirmed with confidence
that the artistic faculty, the sense that distinguishes between acts,
relationships, and things that are ugly and those that are beautiful,
has hitherto been regarded by the social reformer as the Cinderella of
the family - the negligible member of the tri-sisterhood of senses on
whom we rely for our standards of conduct. The moral pointed by the
familiar fairy-tale of the nursery may be not without some bearing on
the stage we have now reached in the evolution of human relationships.
It may be that the future fortunes of the household are to be
retrieved by this Princess in disguise whom we have left sitting among
the ashes and regarded as of no account; and it will not be the first
time in the history of a family, a nation, or a race, that salvation
or rescue has come from an unexpected quarter.
Mankind has probably never been entirely without some vague or
subconscious perception of an ultimate check upon conduct; a high
court whose judgments are irreversible and which delivers its verdicts
only after the laws of right and wrong or truth and falsehood have
been violated; a judiciary that condemns with the judgment of
ugliness, actions that have fought their way through all the lower
courts of conscience. We recall Talleyrand's famous "It is worse
than a crime, it is a blunder," and Ouida's "It is worse
than wicked, it is vulgar," as unconscious admissions of the
ultimate authority of this dimly conceived final court of appeal. At
no time, indeed, has the aesthetic sense been quite inoperative as a
factor in the regulation of private conduct. In the lives of the more
refined members of the human race it has served the purpose of those
finer adjustments in machinery which determine the rate of speed to a
degree of delicacy impossible by the ordinary levers and ratchets. In
domestic life, for example, there occur countless junctures where
problems of conduct arise upon which the moral law offers no very
definite opinion, but on which the aesthetic sense pronounces an
emphatic judgement -says this act is graceful, that act is ugly. We
rebuke unseemly conduct in our children and sometimes in one another,
not by stigmatizing it as wrong, but as "not pretty" or as "undignified."
Again, it is fairly certain that many crimes against society of the
genteeler sort known as manipulation of markets or watering of stock,
have been condoned not only in the consciences of the perpetrators but
in the judgments of the public, by the consideration that they have
been planned and executed in an artistic manner. It is probable that
even our old friend Bill Sykes is not quite insensible to the artist's
pride in the robbing of a till or the "cracking of a crib,"
and would feel agonies of remorse over a piece of work that had fallen
short of his artistic standard in detail and technique.
Yet though in private life men never entirely disregarded the
judgments of the aesthetic sense, it is painfully obvious that the
criteria of conduct it sets up have not been applied with equal
incisiveness and discrimination either to the material structure of
society or to the mutual relationships and attitudes in which men
stand to each other. We tolerate ugliness in our cities that few among
us would endure in our homes. We patiently suffer outrage and violence
upon our sense of the beautiful in the hideous advertisements that
disfigure our railway embankments and country roads, in apparent
unconsciousness that one of the members of the blessed Trinity upon
which our higher life depends, is being insulted and trampled upon. We
seem to have forgotten that if in any real sense the Good, the True
and the Beautiful are convertible terms, we ought to regard ugliness
as immoral, and as untrue to the deepest laws of our being. And it is
not with impunity that we permit ourselves thus to stumble through our
public life and to make mistakes of so atrocious a character. The
words of the late Professor Huxley are as applicable to the conduct of
Society in the collective sense as in the case of an individual man. "Life,"
he said, "may be compared to a game of chess with an unseen
player who never makes a mistake and never pardons one; who makes no
allowance for ignorance of the rules of the game; who would rather
lose than win, but who punishes carelessness equally with trickery and
rewards the valiant and skilful with that lavish generosity which the
strong delight to show."
Is it not evident that we have blundered egregiously in thus
contemning in our public life this youngest member of the group of
senses by whose aid we find our way to the higher levels of being? And
as all mistakes have to be paid for when the day of reckoning comes,
might it not have been expected that this disregard of the beautiful
in material things would work itself out in an insensibility to
ugliness in social relationships and a subsequent blindness to
immorality in public conduct? This at all events is what has happened.
The regard for aesthetic considerations which in private life not only
demands beauty in material things, but undoubtedly provides an
additional sanction to the dictates of conscience and serves to
regulate conduct where the moral law is silent, has utterly failed in
the corporate life of society both in material things and in matters
of policy or behaviour.
But there are not lacking signs to those who keep their ears to the
ground, that the artistic sense in our corporate life, which we may
thank God has never been quite smothered but has only lain dormant, is
at length beginning to assert itself. Men are realizing as they have
never done before, the material ugliness of our public surroundings
and the unsightliness of the contrasts in economic conditions that
distinguish present-day society. What the sense of righteousness,
blinded as it has always been by the dust of class-prejudice and the
crosscurrents of mercantile-economic theories, has not been able to
condemn, the sense that hungers and thirsts for beauty in all its
tangible and intangible forms, revolts at and pronounces intolerable.
We are convinced that this revulsion of the artistic sense at the
unspeakable ugliness of many of the aspects of modern society is an
important contributory to that wave of passion for economic reform
that has laid hold of the souls of men, even of those whose own lots
have been cast in pleasant places. If this is true, it is a
circumstance full of hope and promise. And was the recovery of this
dormant sense for sweetness and harmony that we name aesthetics, not
inevitable as a result of the growth of intelligence? It can only have
been that stupidity that has dogged the footsteps of man ever since he
forsook the lowly path of instinct and started upon the great
adventure of the intellectual life, that has made him insensible to
the violence done to his finer intuitions by the form of society which
he has himself evolved. But stupidity is fortunately one of the human
limitations that tends to cure itself. It is a negative thing like
darkness or ignorance, and disappears before light and understanding.
With the gradual unfolding of the intelligence there could hardly fail
to come a development of the aesthetic faculty, a quickened
sensitiveness not only to the things that are good and true, but to
those that are beautiful in the life of the community as well as
within the circle of private life.
The purpose of this article is to urge economic reformers in general
and Single Taxers in particular to welcome the impetus towards reform
that may lie concealed in this sensitiveness to the ugliness and
vulgarity of much of our wealth-display, this aesthetic nausea which
so many of us feel towards the inequalities of fortune we see around
us; and to realize that it is predisposing the minds of the younger
generation to the study of root causes in a way that theories of
social justice have often failed to do. Human action must always be
guided by reason, but it can only be impelled by sentiment. Nor need
this appeal for a recognition of the judgments of the artistic
sentiment be interpreted as derogating from the importance of the part
that the moral sense must always play in human life. What is intended
is to insist that ugly things, ugly contrasts, and ugly human
relationships are at bottom immoral, and that to some minds the
immorality first reveals itself as an offence against the aesthetic
sense.
That the hunger for righteousness, truth and beauty form the trinity
of motive-forces on which humanity depends for its upward development,
will generally be conceded; but it is probably not sufficiently
understood that an under-development of one of those senses tends to
distort the judgments of the other two. It has sometimes been
recognized that a deficiency of the moral sense or of the scientific
habit of mind limits the sensitiveness to beauty in all its forms; but
it is no less true that an insensitiveness to beauty in tangible and
intangible things, limits the sensibility to right and wrong, and to
truth and error. Only by the recognition of this truth can we explain
to ourselves the strange aberrations of human judgment upon the
actions of men in society and on the economic structure which forms
the framework of our collective life. If ugliness pained us as it
ought to pain moral and truth-loving creatures, we should be moved to
revolt by almost everything we see around us. To the psychologist, the
biography of that great English writer, John Ruskin, is chiefly
interesting as showing how an intense sensitiveness to the beautiful
produced in him at the period of middle age a revulsion at the
ugliness of the social system around him, and turned the whole current
of his life away from the sphere of art criticism where it properly
belonged, into that of economic reform. It was the offence to his
aesthetic sense that first moved him to that passionate outburst of
appeal to the British public to realize the degradation of the mire of
commercialism and low ideals in which it was then sunk, and in which
pure life and noble art had no chance to live.
"That which is highly esteemed among men is an abomination in
the sight of the Lord." When that God-given faculty which
discerns a thing of beauty as a joy for ever, becomes atrophied in an
individual or in a people, the judgments of the moral sense and the
power to perceive truth are inevitably dulled. With a revival of the
aesthetic sense many things that are now "highly esteemed among
men" will be brought to that bar of judgment where the Goddess of
Beauty presides and called upon to show reason for their continued
existence. A new kind of public opinion, reinforced by that sense of
artistic fitness which largely regulates our private Ife, may be
expected to come into operation. We may then ask ourselves why we
should despise the glutton at the dinner table or the strong man who
shoulders his weaker neighbour aside that he may occupy the space that
would accommodate both, and continue to respect him who uses his
superior brain-power to gain an advantage over his less astute
brethren in the economic field. If our aesthetic sense revolts at the
greed of a child who appropriates by force a larger share of a limited
luxury than he can use, it will equally despise the child of a larger
growth who clutches and holds more of nature's bounties than he can
wisely employ. When that vision arrives which only comes with the
sensitiveness to beauty, the essential difference between service and
dis-service, between working and stealing, will be revealed. We shall
no longer respect the man whose wealth is not an exact reflex of the
value of his service to the world. When the Beautiful is restored to
its rightful place with the Good and the True among our scale of
value-standards, it may be regarded as an unseemly and disreputable
thing when we see men appropriating to private uses those forms of
wealth which obviously belong rightfully to society. In short, with
the aesthetic faculties in full operation, we may come to recognize no
essential difference between a man wallowing in unearned wealth, and a
pig wallowing in mud; and when Dame Fashion approves the judgment of
the aesthetic sense as she is likely ultimately to do, the doom of "bad
form" may be pronounced on swollen fortunes as it is now on
ostentation in jewelry. Under pressure of a public opinion of this
kind, how much more easily conditions of economic justice may be made
to prevail. The main part of the opposition at present offered to the
Single Tax movement will probably disappear when Millionaires find
themselves ostracised as vulgarities and offences to our most delicate
and refined sensibilities. And so, at last, through the aid of that
final culture of the spirit which we call the aesthetic sense, we may
have Beauty for ashes, the oil of joy for mourning, and the garment of
praise for the spirit of heaviness.
|