Review of the Book
The Orthocratic State
by John S. Crosby
Alexander MacKendrick
[Reprinted from the Single Tax Review,
March-April 1916]
To men of a reflective turn who are consciously breaking away from
the trammels of the past and reaching out to the larger freedom which
looms upon the horizon of life, there must at times occur the
questions, What will be the ultimate forms of a Society founded upon
righteousness? is there room in the conception of a free people for a
compulsory form of government? is there any logical halting-place in
the aspiration towards political liberty short of complete anarchy or
the negation of all force in government and its replacement by
internal guidance? is it "by Wisdom" (or our lack of it)
that "Kings reign and Princes decree justice, that Princes rule,
and Nobles and all the judges of the earth?" is there a place in
that "far-off Divine event" towards which the whole creation
moves for the thought of even the smallest infringement of spontaneous
action, of the right of a man to manage his own life so long as he
interferes, not with the similar liberty of others?' Below the
surface-consciousness of most. men's minds a vague oscillation is
constantly going on between the craving for complete deliverance from
governmental; interference and the recognition that some interference
will be for ever necessary; that government has a natural right to
exist, some warrant in the constitution of human nature for a certain
as-yet undefined measure of interference with liberty of action.
Many attempts have been made as Mr. Crosby has indicated in the book
published since his lamented death, The Orthocratic State, to
formulate a science of society which may serve as a basis for that art
which men have practised since the dawn of human history, the art of
managing one another's affairs. No such attempts have been entirely
satisfactory, or have seemed to provide a statement of natural law on
which the art of government might safely be based, as our mechanical
arts are based upon their respective sciences. Yet by a healthy
instinct or an intuitive perception of the truth, we have felt assured
that such a justification in natural law for the existence of a State
as distinct from a Society, is discoverable, and that it is not
necessary to assume that the ultimate function of government is to go
gradually out of existence. It seems to us that Mr. Crosby has come
nearer to the discovery of the final justification for compulsion in
government than any sociological writer we know of, and it may be that
he has said the last word that need be spoken on the subject for a
long time to come.
Though every so-called scientific "law" may be but a
postulate forming part of a larger principle as yet unknown to us, its
practical value as a guide to conduct may be incalculable. The Atomic
theory as an ultimate explanation of matter, has been entirely
superseded, yet its usefulness in laboratory experiment is as great
today as when first promulgated. Though Mr. Crosby's discovery (for we
must accord his postulate that title) may not be an ultimate truth, it
will be of large value in rationalizing our conceptions of why a
government exists, what it ought to do, and what it ought to refrain
from doing. When one remembers the chaos of opinion that prevails on
these points, ranging from that of the Socialist on the one hand, who
would make the sphere of government co-extensive with all those
activities by which men come into industrial relationships, to that of
the philosophic Anarchist on the other, who claims the right of each
individual to stand outside of the State if he desires to do so, the
value of a postulate based on the nature of man as a social animal can
hardly be over-estimated. It would indeed be well that both those
classes of philosophers should explain by what right the first
presumes to legislate forcibly for the good of his fellow-men, and on
what ground the second claims the privilege to hold himself apart from
the organized State. The scientific reason for compulsory
State-interference, and the limits on the further side, of individual
freedom, are stated by Mr. Crosby with succinctness and precision.
Assuming that those to whom the book is addressed have outgrown the
condition of "subjects" and risen to the status of "citizens"
it is always a valid question to ask, "what is it that we have
appointed our governments for the purpose of doing? Did we put certain
power into their hands for the doing of certain things and no other
things, or did we place them in authority with carte-blanche
instructions to do for us whatever to them seemed good?" This, as
Mr. Crosby indicates is a vital question, and on our answer to it
depends the conception we shall frame for ourselves of the goal
towards which we ought as members of the State to be consciously
striving.
Mr. Crosby appropriately points out the antithesis between society as
a natural association growing out of the inherent tendency of men to
combine and co-operate and the State as an artificial organization
formed like an instrument for the regulation of conduct. "It is
therefore," our author writes, "upon principles existing in
the nature of things, upon the natural laws of society, that the State
must depend for whatever warrant it may have for its existence or for
the exercise of its power. It follows that an enquiry into the nature
and function of the State involves consideration of the principles by
which men should be guided in their conduct toward one another as
members of that natural association with precedes and must be
distinguished from, the artificial organization known as the State."
Without attempting to follow Mr. Crosby through his inquiry as to the
basis of natural rights, it may suffice to say that he draws the
conclusion that the only inherent natural right discoverable is the
right to life and liberty, the right to be left alone, the right of
non-interference. This necessarily involves the right of self-defence
when that right of free action is interfered with, but as the right of
self-defence inheres not in one man but in every man it follows that
liberty of action is limited by the similar liberty of all. But if one
man cannot legitimately interfere with the freedom of another, can a
number of men or even an organization calling itself a State,
legitimately do so? And is the inherent right of self-defence against
a State as indefeasible and inalienable as that against an individual
man? Or can a State establish a moral basis for its claim to compel
all to submit to its jurisdiction?
To these fundamental questions Mr. Crosby offers a reply which must
commend itself to the seeker for basic truths. "If one man in
defending himself against another thereby interferes with any natural
right of still another, this last may justly defend himself against
such interference however unintentional; and it will be found upon
further consideration that it is the necessity for providing efficient
defence against such interference, against unintentional aggression
arising from individual self-defensive disturbance of public peace and
order, that constitutes the only just warrant for the compulsion
essential to the establishment of the State and the maintenance of
civil power." The right therefore to protect ourselves against
the disturbance of public order involved in the private settlement of
disputes between our fellows, provides the moral reason for compelling
all to become members of an organization which shall guarantee the
liberty of each, and in addition assure all its members of protection
from an atmosphere of strife and disorder.
The central idea round which Mr. Crosby's arguments revolve is
contained in one sentence, "The most that the State can do for
civilization and social progress is to mind its own business." To
discover what that business is, and is not, is the obvious purpose
with which the book has been written. Having found that the initial
justification for compulsory government lies in the necessity for
protection from the disturbances of public order involved in the
private settlements of disputes as to infringements of primary rights,
Mr. Crosby finds other three State functions growing naturally out of
this initial State-function. These are, the protection of private
property, the secure possession of which is part of the primary right
to life and liberty; the discharge of services which are in their
nature of a public character and cannot be performed by individuals,
such as the making of public highways, the establishment of a medium
of exchange or currency, and the holding of an equitable balance
between men's rights to the use of Nature's bounty; and lastly, the
maintenance of the State's own integrity and supreme power. We believe
with the author, that under these four categories all the legitimate
exercises of power on the part of a State may be classed, and that any
action by government that will not fit itself into one or other of
them must be regarded as illegitimate. With such a set of definite
principles before us for delimiting the just functions of government,
it is both interesting and instructive to consider as Mr. Crosby does
in the chapter entitled "Abuses of civil power," the many
and increasing number of governmental activities thrust upon us in
these latter days which can find no justification under any of these
four heads.
That most of our troubles in the political sense arise from
over-government is now probably recognized by candid thinkers, and the
presumption is strong that when an authority does the things it ought
not to do, it will leave undone some of the things it ought to do. The
first task therefore that should occupy the thoughts of those who
would assist in the formation of public opinion is to come to a clear
understanding of the directions in which our governments are "abusing
civil power," or doing things in excess of their legitimate
functions. That the "New Toryism" against which Herbert
Spencer warned the British public thirty years ago as tending to
displace the old idea of liberalism, is rapidly taking hold of the
American mind, is very evident. We are drifting into the assumption
that the purpose of a government is to "do things" for the
good of the people. Out of the quickened sympathy for the under-dogs
in the struggle for existence which our modern culture awakens, we are
grateful to a government which takes the moral responsibility off our
shoulders of righting wrongs - without first enquiring whether these
wrongs are not due to governments having omitted to discharge one of
those functions which alone can justify its existence. Having thus
drifted from the moorings of fundamental principles and lost hold of
the real reasons for a governments authority, there seems no
assignable limit to the things we may permit a government to do, and
so the political creed becomes ever more complex and the burden and
confusion upon the shoulders of the citizen daily more intolerable.
The "new toryism" is upon us, under whatever name it may
masquerade, and if its tyranny is to be thrown off it can only be
through a right understanding of the underlying science of man as a
social animal, on which the art of government ought to be based.
In the light of the four legitimate functions of government
postulated by Mr. Crosby, it is not difficult to perceive that a
government such as that under which we now live, exceeds its rightful
authority in many ways. It exceeds it when it attempts to promote
morality among its citizens. This may seem a hard saying to many
worthy people but a principle to be worth trusting must be trusted,
even though it threaten to slay us. If we concede that the primary
justification for a governments existence is that it may prevent
aggression and preserve liberty, then it follows that a free man has a
right to be immoral if in being so he does not trespass on the rights
to life, property, and liberty of any of his fellows. As Mr. Crosby
says,
"It is the aggression rather than the immorality
with which the State has to deal, and with that for the purpose of
peace and order only, and not for that of morality."
If this should seem like a counsel of despair, consolation should be
found in the faith that if government sufficiently discharges its true
function, that of securing to each of its citizens the inalienable
rights to life, liberty and the pursuit of what they deem happiness,
the natural tendency towards higher moral standards will assert itself
under the stimulus of public conscience. It requires again, no
elaborate argument to show that the State abuses its power when it
interferes with the free-play of economic forces and in any way
deprives a citizen of "a natural market" for his services or
the products of his labors, or interferes with his right to purchase
the products of other men's labor at their natural price, or when it
compels one class of the community in the interests of another class,
to pay a higher price for commodities than would be necessary under
relationships of freedom. Governments can abuse their power when they
set up what Mr. Crosby calls "artificial persons" or
Corporations, endowed with privileges, powers, and immunities which do
not belong to natural persons. When Corporations are entrusted with "public-serving
functions" which government ought itself to perform without
profit, the government falls short of its duty. When it creates
Corporations for the performance of services that are not of a public
character, it exceeds its legitimate function and disturbs that
free-play of demand and supply of service on which industrial health
so much depends.
As to our governments' sins of omission, we must differ with Mr.
Crosby where in one sentence he assumes that "these are
negligible because there is hardly any matter of interest susceptible
to governmental interference that has not been made the subject of
some sort of prohibitive, regulative or stimulative legislation."
Our difference, however, is probably more apparent than real. For if,
as Mr. Crosby admits, the second category of a government's duties
includes that of securing to each citizen the possession of his own
property, then it signally fails in the discharge of this duty when it
omits to draw its revenue from what is obviously the right source, the
value of its land-area and instead, confiscates the earnings of its
citizens or part of those earnings. Nothing is more evident to the
dispassionate and unbiased judgment than that there is an organic
relationship and the need for a public income, and the corporate
wealth which reflects itself in the value of the earth-space occupied
by the governed people. They come into existence together as though by
a pre-destined natural arrangement.
Wherever society has grown to such proportions as to require a
government, land-value proportionate to its needs is there. Where
there is no land-value there is no need of government and no public
income required. When a population disappears, the land-value and the
need of a government disappear together. Like the mother's milk, the
wealth created by the people comes into existence just when the people
require a government and remains so long as the need remains. Mr.
Crosby makes clear in the latter part of the book, his conviction that
governments have failed in their duty under the second category of
functions. They have failed to produce an equilibrium of equity; a
condition where the State would have access to its natural
pocket-book, and where the individual would be absolutely secured in
possession of his property, or all that he has produced, without
diminution or subtraction of any kind. Our governments have failed to
promote morality in that they have themselves been immoral in
permitting and exercising an immoral use of the power entrusted to
them.
If then, we admit the postulate that the initial justification for
the coming into existence of a compulsory form of government is to be
found in the necessity for preserving peace and order, and for
securing each citizen in the possession of all his earnings, the
further question arises, "what will be the ultimate justification
for the permanent continuance of government after communities have
become peaceable and orderly, and the citizen is secured in both his
life and the undiminished products of his labor?" The reply is
that the final, and, as far as we can see, the permanent function of
government will be the provision of public service as postulated in
the third category of functions, and, until nations have learned to
live in amity together, the preservation of its power and integrity as
postulated under the fourth category. When our race has been civilized
in a true sense, and the need for police, military forces, and
law-courts has disappeared, all that will remain to justify the
continued existence of public authorities will be the administration
of those services which in the nature of things individuals cannot do
for themselves - the management of the public utilities, the
preservation of an adequate currency or medium of exchange, and in
general, the wise spending of the publicly created wealth which
expresses itself in the value of the land.
Such a conception of the ultimate and irreducible function of
government is we submit both reasonable and satisfying to the moral
sense. It delivers us from the devil of socialism or the new toryism
on the one hand, and the deep sea of anarchism or the unthinkable
negation of government on the other. It rationalizes and moralizes our
attitude towards the State. It suggests a long-sighted patience with
the problems of the present, and a larger hope for the future. It
contains no seeds of pessimism or despair, but only the promise of a
brighter day when not even the government itself will be permitted to
encroach upon the liberties or earnings of the humblest of its
citizens. Readers of The Orthocratic State will feel
themselves under a deep debt to its author for that greatest of
services, the clarification of thought and the rationalizing of
concepts; and the only remaining regret will be that the opportunity
has for ever passed for the expressing of that gratitude to him who
has so well earned it.
|