Responding to Critics
on the Subject of Interest Theory
Raymond V. McNally
[Reprinted from Land and Freedom,
November-December 1937]
I note some comments in the July-August issue on my article ("What
Is Interest?") which I think demand a reply.
D. L. Thompson states that if I am right in my opinion that what is
termed "interest" is merely "compensation for risk,"
interest rates should be higher, as he believes "the element of
risk has steadily increased since the last industrial breakdown."
I am afraid, however, that such a belief is not substantiated either
by fact or in theory. Anyone who has made a study of business cycles
knows that the element of risk is greatest immediately prior to an
industrial crisis, when speculation has driven values upward to the
breaking point, and is lowest during the period between crises. It is
the wise man who invests during this interim. Your readers will
doubtless recall the fact that commercial interest rates just prior to
the 1929 debacle were at a record height and gradually shaded off as a
new equilibrium was being established. A few years ago at the low
point of the depression, after the terrific liquidation of 1932 (when
business failures were more numerous than in any other year), interest
rates were at the lowest level one-eighth per cent on call loans.
Since that time they have been slowly hardening, corresponding with
the increase in the hazards of doing business not, as Mr. Thompson
contends, since the "last industrial breakdown," but since
the low point of the depression. They will continue to rise, for the
risk element increases as we creep nearer to the next crisis. The
great activity recently in the building industry is a sure indication
that men with capital regard conditions now to be more secure than
they were just prior to or immediately after 1929.
As for Mr. Thompson's claim that the element of time accounts for "interest,"
I would like to refer him again to my article, for he has made no
attempt to meet the arguments that I set up against this particular
idea. And as his error appears to be due to his having confused use
value with economic value, I suggest also that he read the very
enlightening chapters on value in Henry George's The Science of
Political Economy.
Turning now to the letter written by Henry P. Sage, I find him
claiming that the cause of "interest" is the service
rendered by the lender to the borrower which enables the latter to "overcome
the disutility of time" and is not the increased power that labor
receives from capital. But although he has made a valiant effort to
keep clear of the Productivity theory, he cannot help falling into it
when he tries to measure this disutility or inconvenience. He offers
the illustration of a man who, rather than spend a year accumulating
capital, prefers to borrow $500 so he can work his farm immediately At
the end of the year, he is able not only to pay back the principal
with "interest" but to have for himself stock and tools and
several hundred dollars in cash. Now, Mr. Sage wants us to believe
that when this farmer applies capital to land, he can earn more than
he could at some other occupation without capital. But this is rather
doubtful economics, for such a condition is impossible. If a man could
increase his income merely by using capital, a flock of competitors
would be attracted to his occupation who would drive his income down
to what it was working without capital. And if he borrowed capital in
order to obtain an advantage over working without capital and
contracted to pay for that advantage, he would soon find himself
bankrupt. Practical experience supports this statement, for 90 per
cent of those who enter business for themselves eventually fail,
largely because of incompetence. Capital can give nothing to labor
that labor does not already have in itself. A savage, for instance,
would be helpless with a machine in his hands. A man does not use
capital to increase his efficiency, but rather he is first efficient
and that is why he uses capital. In other words, using capital is the
conventional mode of producing wealth, and the man in the illustration
is compelled by competition to employ capital on this type of farm if
he is to remain in the market. This may be difficult to perceive, for
we are so accustomed to the schoolboy formula that "capital aids
labor to produce wealth." Mr. Sage's belief that labor gains from
the use of capital is based on the assumption that, as an alternative
to borrowing, one must engage in an inferior occupation in order to
accumulate capital, as though capital had the power to determine one's
ability or the productiveness of any occupation. Such a notion is
socialistic and contrary to fact. This assumption is the pitfall of
all productivity theorists. It is labor only that determines the
character of industry. Capital merely represents the method of labor
or the direction that labor takes in production.
When we come to understand the true nature of capital, we shall see
that one borrows instead of accumulating capital oneself, not to gain
an advantage over working without capital, but because of the
convenience of having it at a particular time. All that can be
afforded in return for this convenience is compensation for risk, for
one's income as a laborer, other things being equal, is determined
entirely by one's own efforts.
|