What is Interest?
Raymond V. McNally
[Reprinted from Land and Freedom, May-June
1937]
Interest is commonly referred to in much the same way as the terms "money"
and "property" glibly, without any definite understanding of
what it really is and what causes it. Interest is the return for the
use of capital," people say, believing that with this simple
assertion they have completely disposed of the matter. If pressed to
explain the cause of interest, they amiably accept any plausible
theory with the comment that interest is of no great importance
anyway. Many Georgeists, confident that they know the whole truth
because of their acceptance of Henry George's correlation of the law
of rent and the law of wages, also assume this unscientific attitude,
without realizing that such complacency is dangerous in the light of
the confusion relating to economic matters that pervades the world
today. As George insisted upon treating economics as a science, they
are actually violating the trust that he reposed in those who followed
him to carry further the application of the general principles that he
laid down, wherever necessary. To many people, the Marxists
particularly, the question of interest is highly important and any
unscientific explanation of it tends to discredit in their minds even
the law of rent and the law of wages.
Some Georgeists blindly accept George's law of interest without fully
understanding it, as one might a religious tenet. Others profess
belief in it but under pressure of discussion, reveal a belief in
something entirely different. Still others, while frankly rejecting
his theory, are seen to hold various other ideas that fail to stand up
under examination. Is it not significant that while there is a general
agreement among economists on the law of rent, there is none on the
question of interest? The interest problem has plagued the human race
from ancient times right down to the present day, and although an
enormous amount of literature has been written on the subject, it has
not yet been satisfactorily solved. Obviously the failure to agree is
due largely to a confusion of terminology and a misuse of words. Now,
I am well aware of the fact that the subject of interest cannot be
treated thoroughly in the limited space of a single article, and it
may be that I shall not do full justice to the different theories and
the various phases of each that have been advanced by many different
economists. Yet all of these theories cannot be correct. While each is
based on a different principle, in some respects they are quite
similar. Therefore, I shall confine myself to a discussion of a few of
the more prominent theories, disclosing the errors that are peculiar
to each and pointing out the fundamental error that is common to all
of them.
Let us begin by stating what economists mean by interest. It is the
income that accrues to all capital in the production of wealth,
regardless of its nature, above its replacement value. It includes all
returns from the use of capital, whether the capital is used by the
owner or borrower, but excludes compensation for risk and for wear and
tear obsolescence. We are not seeking the cause of any particular rate
of interest but of the general rate of interest. Thus, we must view
capital in the general sense, that is, as it relates to the community
and not to an individual, for the income that an individual may
acquire from the use of his capital might not add to the sum total of
wealth. Wealth consists of tangible goods produced by labor when
applied to land, and capital represents that part of wealth that is
not consumed immediately but that is employed by labor in order to
obtain more wealth. We must be careful to avoid at the same time any
reference to whether interest is right or wrong until after we have
reached our conclusions, for economic science is not concerned with
the question of morals.
The phenomenon of barren capital yielding a return to the lender who
rendered no service for it first engaged the attention of philosophers
Plato, Aristotle, Cicero and others who condemned it as unjust. After
the collapse of Rome, the Roman Catholic Church continued the attack
on it and so strong was its authority that legislation outlawing it
was passed throughout all Christendom. Not concerning themselves in
the least with any logical analysis of interest nor with determining
the exact cause of it, the protest of the canonists, like that of the
ancient philosophers, was steeped entirely in considerations of
justice and benevolence, for they were aroused by what they considered
the injustice of inanimate things enjoying a continuous existence and
in addition yielding an increase to those who did nothing to earn it.
During all of this time, however, in spite of the ecclesiastical
denunciation and the civil laws, the phenomenon of interest persisted
in industrial life, because it was a natural part of the economic
organism and could not be abolished by men. The canonists found it
imperative, therefore, to support their hostility with something more
than appeals to the sacred writings of the New Testament and those of
the famous philosophers. Thomas Aquinas was probably the first of the
Church fathers to take a theoretical approach to the problem by
refuting the idea that there was an independent use of capital, that
deserved a reward, aside from its actual consumption. But like those
who followed him, his pronouncements were little more than an appeal
to the moral aspects of the problem, for he did not explain the
phenomenon of interest. Despite the inadequacies of the canonists'
arguments, however, they seemed to be strong enough to hold their
opponents in check. Calvin, the reformer, one of these opponents,
justified interest on the grounds that the lender could put his money
into land which would yield him an income, overlooking the fact that
the interest rate would first have to be determined before the selling
value of the land could be computed. Weak as the arguments of the
opposition were, they did influence thought and encouraged others to
carry on the work of criticism.
The persistence of the phenomenon of interest in economic life and
the lessening of the authority of the Church that resulted from the
religious and political upheavals during the middle ages, permitted
economists to write freely on the subject purely from the economic
angle. Very few of them approached the problem, however, with entirely
open minds. Most of them accepted interest as a fact, and their
inquiries (with the exception of the Rodbertus and Karl Marx school of
writers) consisted in strenuous efforts to justify it. None of them
thought of questioning its reality not even the socialist.
The simple claim that interest is the reward for the use of capital
has been developed by some economists into very elaborate theories
that have been achieved through a process of mental acrobatics, and
any attempt to follow their long-winded and tortuous dialectics leaves
one well nigh exhausted and almost incapable of further thought on the
subject. The Say-Hermann school assumed in the case of the loan of
capital that what was transferred to the borrower was not the capital
itself but an independent use of the capital. The payment for the use
of the capital was said to be interest. For instance, if A lent B a
plow for a year and at the end of that time received back a new plow
to replace the one that was worn out and part of B's crops as well, it
was assumed that A received back the same plow he had lent and that
the crops represented interest or payment for the use of that plow.
But it can readily be seen that B had not only the use of the plow but
the plow itself, and that what he returned to A was not the same plow
but another equally as good. In other words, B wore the plow out
during the year by using it and paid for the use of it by returning a
new plow to A. What then can we regard the payment of part of his
crops to represent? Surely we cannot assume that there are two
distinct uses attaching to the loan of the plow. The using of it is
the same thing as its consumption. If B instead of borrowing had
bought the plow, he would have paid A at once a value that was
equivalent to a new plow equally as good; but when he borrowed he paid
A not only a new plow of equal value but part of his crops as well.
Why? If it is said that this additional payment was for the delay in
replacing the plow, then we are attributing interest, not to the use
of the plow, but to the element of time, which is an entirely
different matter. But inadequate as the use theory obviously is, as an
explanation of interest, it leads us directly and indirectly into
other theories.
One of them is the Abstinence theory of which N. W. Senior appears to
be the originator. According to it, interest is the reward for
abstaining from the immediate consumption of the results of one's
labor. But abstinence in itself is not productive. It is a negative
quality.
If a man saves the fruits of his labor in the form of money and keeps
it locked up in a tin box, he has exercised as much abstinence as
though he had lent it, yet he will expect no increase from it. It is
said that when a man accumulates capital and lends it to another, he
has rendered a service. But does not the second man render a service
also by keeping it safely and returning it intact? In fact, the second
service may be greater than the first. If the first man retained his
capital, he would have the trouble of caring for it. It would
deteriorate otherwise and eventually disappear. Capital, therefore, to
be maintained must be used, and the borrower pays his debt in full
when he replenishes or replaces the capital and returns it to the
lender. The use is offset by the replacement. If the borrower must pay
an additional sum as interest, is he not robbed? So the Marxist
believes, who insists that interest accrues at the expense of labor.
In my opinion, those who hold the Abstinence theory do not
sufficiently meet the arguments of the Marxist.
Senior claimed that abstinence was a factor in production and that
indemnification for the sacrifice involved in it was an element in the
cost of production. In other words, capital is the result of two kinds
of sacrifice one involved in the labor directed to its production and
one involved in the postponement of present enjoyment. This is
obviously a double calculation. To make this point clearer, let us
suppose an owner of capital uses it himself to produce more wealth.
Out of the wealth produced, he pays himself wages for his labor and
compensation for the effort he exerted in making the capital, which
consists merely of its replacement value. Now, if he claims an
additional sum for having abstained in the first place from
immediately consuming his wealth instead of accumulating it in the
form of wealth, he is overlooking the fact that without the aid of the
capital his wages would not have been so great. He can include one or
the other sacrifice in the cost of production but he cannot include
both.
Our contemporary, Prof. Harry Gunnison Brown, in a discussion of
interest in his Economic Basis of Tax Reform unfortunately
falls into a similar error. He states on page 32 that an added annual
output of industry is made possible by that person or persons "whose
saving, whose excess of production over consumption, brought the
capital into existence." He recognizes that savings of the
individual are the result of an excess of production over consumption
in other words, that savings and excess production are one and the
same thing. Yet he seems to overlook this fact when he insists that
the individual receive not only wages for that excess production but
also compensation or interest for the savings. Now, savings of course
explain the existence of capital but they do not explain how interest
arises. It is true, as Prof. Brown points out, that labor can produce
more with capital than without it, but to insist that the increase or
any part of it is due to the owner of capital, is to assume that the
person who uses it is not capable himself of saving part of the
results of his own labor; that saving is the result of superior
qualities or of a superior technique. This then would make the
question one of wages and not of interest. If it is claimed that some
people cannot afford to save, that they are forced to consume all that
they produce and that, therefore, those who are in a more fortunate
position render a real service by making their savings available for
use in production, then what we are discussing is not capital but
monopoly.
It is only fair to point out here that Prof. Brown admits in his
earlier book, Economic Science and the Common Welfare, that
saving is not limited to one class but is open to all and that those
who use capital can save themselves and become the owners of their own
capital. He concedes that some people would save even though there
were no prospect of reaping a reward for their old age and future
security. He knows, too, that some people find it easy to save, while
others find it hard, regardless of whether they are rich or poor. Yet
those who find it hard to save receive no greater return on their
capital. The millionaire does not suffer as much pain as the poor man
when he saves in fact saving might be a real pleasure and realizing
that the phrase "pain of saving" is rather too strong to
apply generally, Prof. Brown chooses to use the expression "impatience"
or "time-preference." At the same time, he perceives that "impatience"
or "time-preference" varies with different people and that
because of its lack of universality, it cannot serve as a reliable
basis of interest. Consequently, he narrows the element of "impatience"
down to that of the "marginal" saver that is, the person who
will not save unless he receives a compensation for so doing and
assumes that if it were not for this -"marginal" saving,
there would not be sufficient capital furnished for profitable
enterprise. This is an arbitrary assumption, for it can be claimed
with equal assurance that this "marginal" saving furnished
rather too much capital. Interest then is regarded here as being
caused not by all abstinence but only by that of the "marginal"
saver; and although he has tried to avoid making the question one of
monopoly, he has gone right around in a circle and met himself coming
back, so to speak. In other words, the "marginal" saver
holds the balance of power and the socialist's claim of exploitation,
according to this reasoning, is sustained.
Realizing the weakness of his position because of the negative
character of abstinence, Prof. Brown has sought to save himself by
attributing interest directly to the productivity of capital. By the
productivity of capital he does not mean that capital possesses the
power to reproduce itself plus an increase but that labor can produce
more with the aid of capital than without it, and this increase is
interest. This is merely an assertion, for although Prof. Brown has
devoted 36 pages in his Economic Science and the Common Welfare
to a discussion of the cause of interest, he has succeeded only in
showing how capital is accumulated and how capital aids labor. But
although he has not proved interest, he proceeds to show how various
psychological factors influence the rate of interest to such an extent
that the whole increase in production due to the use of capital might
not necessarily go to capital. Here he brings in another element the
element of time by estimating the desirability of present goods (which
could be bought with one's savings) as compared with future goods (the
product obtained with the use of capital). And although he is aware
that no two men necessarily act alike under similar circumstances, he
attempts to draw a general principle from probabilities, clearly
revealing the influence exerted on him by Jevons and the Austrian
economists. Thus his theory of interest appears to be a curious,
eclectic blending of the Abstinence, Productivity and Time theories.
The Time theory, as developed by Eugen V. Bohm-Bawerk, briefly is
this: Present goods are valued more highly than future goods. For
instance, $100 now is equivalent to say $105 a year hence, the
difference being interest. But it is not at all conclusive that
present goods are always valued higher than future goods. It depends
entirely on individual feelings. $100 a year hence might seem to me to
be much more desirable than $100 now, if I had no immediate use for it
but did contemplate a very important use for it in the future. If I
did require an additional $5, it would be because I wished to be
compensated for the risk involved in waiting a year before I used my
money, but this would not be interest. This Time theory is based on
the utility theory of value which means that a thing derives its value
from the intensity of individual desire measured by its marginal or
lowest degree of usefulness. But marginal utility differs in the case
of individuals.
No matter how strenuously Bohm-Bawerk strives to make his value
theory stand on its own feet, he is forced time and again to admit
that the marginal utility of a thing depends in the last analysis on
its scarcity which involves, as we know, human exertion. Human
exertion stands supreme in this case, for while utility may be
measured by exertion, exertion is never measured by utility. Desire
cannot be measured in itself but only by the resistance it will
overcome and this resistance to the gratification of desire is the
pain of exertion. Therefore, the value of a thing depends not on its
marginal utility but on the amount of exertion necessary to produce a
similar thing. The futility of trying to draw a general principle from
psychological probabilities is clearly shown in both the Abstinence
and Time theories of interest. This probably explains why Bohm-Bawerk
used so much space in his "Positive Theory of Capital" in
his attempt to prove his point, for his book reads more like a
treatise on psychology than a discussion of economics. But while
psychology might aid us in explaining certain relative economic
phenomena (such as why one occupation will pay a higher wage than
another), economic science has nothing to do with the purely
subjective feelings and desires of individuals, from which no absolute
laws can be deduced.
The Productivity theory, which we shall now consider, has always been
a popular one because at first glance it appears so plausible. That
labor can produce more with capital than without it seems self-evident
and so its adherents ascribe the increase to the power that resides in
capital. As to just what this power is or where it comes from there is
no clear idea. Before proceeding, it might be well to determine what
the "productive power" of capital means. There are two
possible meanings. It may mean that capital aids labor to produce more
goods and that such goods have more value than the capital consumed in
their production, the increase being inter- est. There is no denying
the fact that labor can produce more goods with the aid of capital
than without it, but in order to prove interest, we must show that the
value of these goods is greater than the capital consumed in their
making. It does not necessarily follow that a greater quantity of
goods is more valuable than a smaller quantity. Such a claim would
have to be demonstrated.
Let us suppose that A can catch 3 fish a day with his bare hands but
finally decides to spend a day to make himself a fishing pole which
will last the five days of a six-day working week. With this pole he
can catch 10 fish a day, so that at the end of the five days when the
pole will be worn out, he will have 50 fish and will take the last day
to make himself a new pole. Without the pole he could only catch 15
fish and so he has gained an increase of 35. The productivity
theorists assume that this increase is interest, and if the 50 fish
represent a value greater than that of the 15 fish caught with the
bare hands, this would be true. But no more exertion was required of A
to catch 50 fish with the pole than to catch 15 with his bare hands.
As value is measured by exertion and nothing else, the 50 fish is
equivalent in value to the 15 fish and there is nothing left for
interest. But it may be said that if A had lent his pole, he could
have procured an increase from it. Let us assume then that A lends his
pole to B for a week instead of using it himself. At the end of the
five days, B will have 50 fish and will take the last day to make a
new pole to return to A. Has B gained at the expense of A by this
transaction? A in the meantime has taken the first day to make himself
another pole which would last five days. At the end of the week he
will stand in the same position as though he had not lent his pole
namely, 50 fish and a new pole which he received from B. B, on the
other hand, if he had borrowed, could have made a pole for himself. It
must be assumed of course that B is able to make a pole as well as A,
for otherwise our illustration would be one of superior skill and not
of capital, and the question would be one of wages and not of
interest. He would use the pole for the five days it would last and
have 50 fish, exactly the same number he would have had if he had
borrowed. Thus, B has gained nothing to the loss of A and need not pay
any interest and A has gained no increase from lending. Where and how
does interest arise then?
The other meaning of the "productive power" of capital is
this: Capital possesses a power in itself of producing more value than
it has in itself. Capital of course is productive because it enables
labor to produce goods more efficiently, but that is a different thing
from asserting that capital enables labor to produce more value.
Capital in the physical sense, being the product of land and labor,
consists of both natural and human powers.
What gives rise to the value of capital, however, is not the natural
power but the human power therein which manifests itself through
actual exertion when the capital is used. For that reason then and
despite the fact that George Gunton in his Wealth and Progress,
ridiculed the idea that capital was "stored-up labor" (human
energy could only be stored up in a human being, he said), we are safe
in saying, in the value sense, that capital formulation is the storing
up of labor in concrete form. But by no stretch of the imagination can
we say that when this energy is released through the use of the
capital a value is created greater than its own value, and, therefore,
we cannot explain interest by adopting this particular meaning of "productive
capital."
If Henry George had attacked Bastiat's celebrated illustration of the
plane in Progress and Poverty from the standpoint of natural
interest instead of loan interest, he might never have chosen the
reproductive forces of nature as constituting the cause of interest,
thus avoiding the violation of some of his own fundamental concepts.
In the first place, he had insisted time and again that capital was
not an independent factor but the product of labor and that labor was
the only active factor. Secondly, he had overlooked the fact that he
had definitely named labor as the only source of value and that to
attribute any value creation to the natural powers was a
contradiction. Furthermore, in his illustration of the calf growing
into a cow, he appeared to assume that the borrower was not in a
position also to avail himself of the natural forces, making the
illustration, therefore, one of monopoly and not one of capital. If
the borrower had free access to nature, he could have produced a calf
as well as the lender and cared for it until it had reached maturity,
so that any increase due to nature would have been absorbed and freed
him of the necessity of paying interest.
His statement that if wine were put away, at the end of the year it
would have increased in value because of the improved quality
unfortunately confused economic value with use value. He pointed out
in his The Science of Political Economy that the value of a
thing was not intrinsic that is, it had nothing to do with its
substance but was due to the amount of exertion that would be required
to reproduce it. The increase in the value of the wine was not due to
its improved quality but to the labor expended in its production, for
if a man makes wine and puts it away, his production has not stopped
but continues for waiting is a part of human exertion until the end of
the year. And even though the natural forces were capable of creating
a value, George did not prove that the cow was any more valuable than
the calf plus the action of nature, plus the labor expended in caring
for it. It was merely an assertion. He was arbitrary also in assuming
that the plane in Bastiat's illustration contained no vital force of
nature, which helps man to produce. What is the difference between the
reproductive force of nature in plant and animal life and the chemical
and geologic forces in such things as poles, concrete, planes and
machines? Isn't water power, for instance, a force outside of man
himself even though it is not reproductive in character?
The error in all of this, however, is akin to the error of the
Austrian economists in bringing psychological factors into economics.
Economic science is not concerned with how nature helps man to produce
wealth, for it has nothing to do with the physical laws of production.
It is interested only in the laws of distribution which are based on a
fundamental law of human nature, that men seek to satisfy their
desires with the least amount of exertion. But while it may be said
that this law is psychological and physiological, it is not peculiar
to these sciences but is a universal law the law that motion tends to
seek a straight line or the line of least resistance and is,
therefore, common to all of the sciences, such as mathematics,
chemistry, physics, geology, and biology.
The various schools of thought regarding interest have attempted to
deduce a general law from a relative concept. Capital is not an
independent factor like land and labor, for it can be received into
both of these. Land and labor are absolute concepts and the returns
that they yield must necessarily yield absolute returns. On the other
hand, capital, being a relative concept and representing only a use to
which wealth is put, must necessarily yield relative returns. As
absolute returns and relative returns cannot logically stand on a
parity with one another, it is incorrect to say that wealth is
distributed into rent, wages and interest. Strictly speaking, wealth
is distributed only in two ways, namely, rent and wages, and the only
laws with which economic science is concerned then are those of rent
and wages. We can no more deduce a general law of interest than we can
deduce a general law of particular wages. The phenomenon in economic
life that appears to be interest but which economic science is not
able to locate is very likely nothing else but compensation for risk,
a relative return to capital analogous to the return that equalizes
the hazards and disagreeableness of various kinds of labor.
When a man locks his money up, he does so because he fears the risk
involved in lending it. When he lends it, he demands not interest in
the economic sense but compensation for risk. It is interesting to
note that Bohm-Bawerk on page 423 says that "the greater security
of the investment, again, and the prospect of future rise in value,
keeps the rate of interest in immovables low; and considerations
closely akin to this account for the present lower return of interest
on state bonds, preferences, etc. payable in gold as compared with
those payable in silver or paper," so that it seems in spite of
the fact that he believes there is such a thing as interest, he is
forced to link it up with the compensation for risk, and that
compensation for risk varies according to the different employments of
capital appears to support the conclusion that the return to capital
is not absolute but relative. The burden of proving that there is such
a thing as interest in the economic sense, therefore, and that it is
unjust, rests entirely with the Marxist and other opponents of
interest.
|