The Unearned Increment: Its Nature
Arthur James Ogilvy
[A chapter from the book A Colonist's Plea for
Land Nationalisation, published in 1901 by the Land
Nationalisation Society, London]
Let us begin by taking the unearned increment in its simplest and
clearest form.
Suppose I buy Government land at $1 per acre, and quietly holding on
while roads are being pushed forward, settlement extending and land
values rising, refuse offer after offer till the price reaches 2, when
I sell out. Of these 2, one I have acquired by direct purchase; 1
worth of money for 1 worth of land; but the other I have done nothing
to acquire.
It is not interest on the purchase-money, for interest is payment for
the use of capital, and comes out of the use. Who would expect
interest on money tied up in an old rag? There has been no use here.
It is not compensation for risk, for the land could not disappear or
deteriorate, and was sure to be wanted.
It may be quite right for all that, that I should have it. That is
not the point at present. The point at present is simply to explain
the term, and to show not only what it directly means, but what it
indirectly implies, for it implies a great deal much more than most
people have any idea of.
I have neither done anything to create this increase of value nor
rendered any service in return for it. If a sovereign were suddenly to
drop into my pocket from the sky, it would not be more completely
unearned.
But it has not only been unearned. If that were all, it would be no
great matter. If, like the sovereign, it had dropped from the sky,
then, though I might be undeservedly the richer, nobody else would be
the poorer. My gain would be a clear addition to the sum total of
human wealth, out of which others besides myself would in one way or
another derive benefit; and, whether or not whatever benefits one
without injuring another is fair subject for congratulation.
But it has not only been unearned; it has been drawn from the
earnings of others. My gain is others loss.
If I sell goods or perform work for another, then no matter how high
I may charge for the goods or the work, I am rendering goods for
goods, service for service, earnings for earnings. What I offer is my
labour, or the fruits of it, and as the public are free to get the
same goods or services elsewhere if my terms don't suit, or to go
without them, the fact of their accepting my terms shows that the
thing I offer is, under the circumstances, worth the money.
But in the case of this unearned increment on land there is no
pretence of any exchange. I offer for it neither labour nor the
produce of labour. All I do is to place my hand on a certain portion
of the earth's surface, and say, "No one shall use this without
paying me for the mere permission to use it." I am rendering no
more service in return for this extra pound, either to the purchaser
or to society, than if I had acquired exclusive title to the air, and
charged people for permission to breathe. And if, instead of selling
my land for an additional pound, I let it at a proportionately
additional rent the principle would be the same.
The increase of value in my land has arisen from the execution of
public works and increase of population, causing an increased demand
for the land; in other words, it has arisen from the national
progress; and I, so far from aiding in this progress have actually
hindered it, by keeping my property locked up and so forcing on
intending producers to inferior or less accessible lands; and by
holding so much land back have helped to make land so much scarcer,
and, therefore, so much dearer, and so have helped to increase the
tribute which industry has to pay to monopoly for the mere privilege
of exerting itself.
I have employed my land not as an instrument of production, but as a
means of extortion. I have bought it, not to use but to prevent other
people from using it without my purchased leave; not to earn anything
by it but to obtain the power of demanding the earnings of others.
Suppose certain parties, knowing that a road would shortly be made
into a particular region, bought from Government the privilege of
placing bars across the road (when made) and forbidding anybody to
pass until he had paid toll; toll not (as under the old State tolls)
to pay for the maintenance of the road, but toll for the mere
permission to pass along the road. Every one would recognise that this
toll was pure blackmail and not earnings, and the obstructors mere
parasites licensed to prey upon the public. But where is the
difference between blocking the road and blocking the land that the
roads lead to? Where is the difference between levying blackmail on
the transport of goods and levying it on their production?
But it will be said, "It was with real earnings that I bought
the right to demand this payment."
True. But the point is that whether I bought it or stole it, the
thing I have bought or stolen is the privilege of levying blackmail
upon industry; of demanding something and giving nothing in return; of
laying my hand on the earth's surface and saying to all and sundry, "Give
me of the produce of your labour, or be off with you; so much a year
if I choose to let it; so much in a lump sum if I prefer to sell it."
Whichever of the two forms the demand assumes it is called by
political economists "rent," and by that name I shall
henceforth call it, because that is the accepted name, and because
there is no other compact and handy term by which to express it; but
it is not to be confounded with rent in the legal and commercial
sense, which includes interest on the cost of improvements. The rent I
shall mean is economic rent only; the price charged for the mere use
of the land as such, either without any improvements or apart from
them: I shall mean "ground rent" in short.
The fact that it was with real earnings that I bought the land for
which I charge rent does not make rent earnings. I may invest earnings
in buying a share in a pirate vessel (as a great writer puts it), but
the proceeds of piracy are not therefore earnings.
It is the nature of the business whereby I make money, and not the
manner in which I got into it that makes the difference between
earnings and appropriation.
Earnings mean taking payment for goods or service rendered;
appropriation means taking something and giving nothing in return; no
matter whether the taking be legal or illegal, or how I acquired the
privilege of taking. Anyone can recognise that it is one thing to
charge for the fish I caught in the sea, and quite another thing to
charge for permission to fish in the sea; one thing to charge for
produce I have raised from the land, and quite another thing to charge
for permission to raise produce from land.
"Still I have the right to make this charge?"
I am not disputing that.
If Government, with the full consent of the governed, issued licenses
authorising to rob on the highway, the robbers, I suppose, would be
justified in acting on their privilege; but their gains, all the same,
would be appropriation and not earnings, no matter how high they paid
for their license or how honestly they came by the money to pay for
it. And if the public, disgusted with the system, demanded its
immediate abolition, the robbers would have a claim to compensation,
but their compensation would have to be assessed, not by the amount of
plunder they had expected to make, but by the fee they had paid for
their license and the actual loss to which, in one way or another,
they had been put by the sudden abolition of a privilege they had
honestly paid for.
But it will be said, "Rent is the result of a free contract."
Is it? The Italian peasant who agrees to pay to the brigand on the
mountain so much a year in consideration of not being robbed makes a
contract, but is it a free contract? If he refuses to pay it the
brigand will take his earnings; if the applicant for land refuses to
pay rent the landlord will refuse to let him make any earnings. Where
is the great difference between the two capes? There is a contract in
each case, and the one is about as free as the other.
In neither case is anything given in return for the payment received,
except permission to work unmolested in a particular place.
"But," it will be said "in practice the rent of an
estate represents real earnings in the shape of improvements made, as
well as mere permission to use the land, and how can you separate the
two values."
Not only is it quite possible to separate them, but the thing is
often done. In London, for instance, the ground rent and the rent for
the house often belong to quite different persons. In Ulster, again,
the retiring tenant receives the value of his improvements while the
landlord keeps the value of the land. And in America, I am told, the
land and the improvements are assessed separately and taxed
separately.
But all this has really nothing to do with the subject in hand. My
concern at present is simply to explain the nature of the unearned
increment.
Whether the value of land and the value of the improvements can be
separated or not, they are quite distinct elements, just as in a glass
of grog, the brandy is brandy and the water water, each with its own
distinctive properties and effects, notwithstanding their
indistinguishable corn-mixture; and he therefore who lets land levies
blackmail upon industry by charging for something which represents no
service at all, none the less that at the same time he charges for
something else that does represent service.
No doubt there are many other things besides land in which a monopoly
of the article will enable the possessor to levy something resembling
blackmail; but there are points of difference that distinguish them
all from the pure and simple appropriation of land monopoly.
The first is that none of them excludes other people from making a
living or from making earnings to any extent by other means than the
article monopolised.
If by a day's labour or by pure accident I find a diamond, I may ask
a price entirely disproportionate to the value of my labour; but then
the public need not buy my diamond unless they like. My finding a
diamond does not prevent other people from looking for diamonds with
as much chance of finding them as I had, and, if they don't think they
are likely to find any by looking for them they can go without, and be
none the worse.
But every piece of land appropriated shuts out so many other people
from that land, and as all the land (practically speaking) is
appropriated, or in one way or another out of reach of the masses,
they are at the mercy of the landholders, and have no choice but
either to rent it from them as tenants or work for them as labourers
on the hardest terms to which competition can drive them ; which means
that the landowner has the power of appropriating the greater part of
their earnings in return for the mere permission to them to earn
anything.
Or suppose that, instead of finding a diamond, I buy tin, and that
next week the price goes up to double here there is an additional
distinction between my gains and the land speculator's; for not only
are the public under no compulsion to buy tin (while they are to rent
land), and not only does tin represent the results of labour, and so
represent earnings (which land does not), but the magnitude of my gain
in most cases represents compensation for great risk.
The earnings of farmers and of miners may average the same, but the
farmers' average is made up of pretty equal profits all round, while
the miners' average is made up of a few big prizes and many blanks.
And what applies to the miner applies also to the speculator in mining
products. His occasional large profits represent compensation for
great risks, and is thus as much of the nature of insurance as of
profit.
No one would think of either mining or speculating in mining
products, unless the many blanks were compensated by occasional large
prizes. They are the necessary inducements to engage in those
callings, and therefore fair earnings when they come. Land, however,
is not a speculation in this sense (though even if it were, its
profits would still be appropriation and not earnings for reasons
already given); it is a sure investment in the sense that it is
subject to no extraordinary risks: to no more risks, that is, than
such as are inseparable from all human enterprise, even the safest.
The value of land, as of everything else, will oscillate within
certain limits, and even in some exceptional cases, as in the sudden
diversion of traffic, fall for an indefinitely prolonged period; but
these occasional or exceptional perturbations are but as the advance
and recession of the waves in a flowing tide. The tide still comes in.
In every country which has any enterprise and progress, land values
must rise. The movement may be fast or slow, continuous or
interrupted, but it is up not down.
There is not a single factor in a nation's progress that does not add
to the value of land. Every road improved and railway laid down; every
machine invented and process perfected; every opening of new markets;
every improvement in fiscal policy, in order and good Government, in
the knowledge and skill, in the morals, manners, and even numbers of
the people, every conceivable element, in short that adds to the
productiveness of industry, adds to the value of land, and increases
the tribute which monopoly can wring from industry; which the man who
merely owns the land can exact from him who uses it for the mere
permission to use it.
This is why the gradual rise of land value or rent (ground rent only,
remember), is called the unearned increment.
So far for its nature. Our next consideration will be its magnitude.
The Unearned Increment: Its Magnitude
Under the system prevailing all over the civilised world every
country is appropriated by a (comparatively) few owners.
What these owners do with the land is a matter the State concerns
itself very little about. Whether they occupy and use it themselves,
or let it to a tenant and live in idleness on the fruits of his
labour; whether they cultivate it like a garden, making it yield
abundant wealth and maintain hundreds of families, or leave it in a
state of nature to carry sheep, excluding the whole rising tide of
population from the opportunity of developing its boundless resources
because the sheep pay them rather better; whether they open out the
mineral treasures hidden in its depths or lock them up by demanding
such exorbitant royalties that enterprise either will not attempt the
work, or attempts and fails; whether they construct factories and
build cities upon it, or turn out the whole population and burn down
their dwellings (as in the Scottish Highlands) because a foreign
millionaire offers them a higher price for the privilege of turning it
into a wilderness to shoot deer in than the children of the soil can
give for the mere privilege of earning a living; all these things the
State regards as matters of quite secondary consideration with which
it is not called upon to interpose, because that would be interfering
with the "sacred rights" of property.
The one thing it does concern itself energetically about is to
establish "the sacred rights" as fast as possible and in all
directions, and ensure that every acre shall have its blackmailer
privileged to exclude everybody else from the land he has acquired
possession of, and to forbid access to all industry except on payment
of the heaviest toll which the keenest competition can compel.
The whole country (that is the whole country worth occupying at any
given moment) being thus apportioned amongst these privileged few,
they are masters of the situation. The first thing a man requires is
room to stand in; and there is no unappropriated room available for
the purpose. If he stands on private land he is liable to an action
for trespass. If he goes out into the street, the policeman may order
him to move on. When night comes on, matters are worse. If he sleeps
on somebody's premises he can be apprehended for being on the premises
for an unlawful purpose. If he sleeps in the bush he may be locked up
as a vagrant without any visible means of support. The State insists
that he shall pay blackmail to somebody; not payment for service of
any sort rendered, but payment for the mere permission to be
somewhere.
Land is the basis of all industry.
All industry consists either
1. In extracting the raw materials of wealth from the land; or
2. In working up, shifting about, or distributing these materials, or
in aiding in one way or another some of these processes.
We shall call the one class primary and the other secondary
industries.
Farming and mining are the chief examples of the primaries. As to the
secondaries, they are legion; and not only are all the materials these
last have to operate upon drawn from the land, but so are the tools
they work with as well as the food the workmen consume.
It is clear that the extent of the secondary industries will be
strictly limited by the primaries; that is, there can be no more
persons engaged in working up, shifting about and distributing
materials than there are materials (extracted from the land) for them
to work up, shift about and distribute and not only is the extent of
the secondaries determined by the extent of the primaries, but so also
are the profits in the secondaries determined by the profits in the
primaries.
Materials must be extracted (or produced) from the land before they
can be put to any further use, and men will not leave this necessary
preliminary work to take to the secondary work unless they can make as
much by the new industry as they could by the old; and they cannot
hope to make more, because if they did, the opening in the secondary
industries being strictly limited, competitors would at once flock in
and bring their profits down.
If profits in the primary industries are high, that is, if the land
yields abundantly, and no one steps in to appropriate the fruits,
profits in the secondaries will be high too, for otherwise people
would leave the secondaries and betake themselves to the land.
If, on the other hand, profits in the primaries are low that is, if
either nature is niggardly or someone (the landlord for instance)
appropriates the fruits, profits in the secondaries will be low too;
for otherwise people would leave the land and crowd into the
secondaries till they brought profits down. Now, if all the land is
held by a comparatively few people (as is the case) then since the
land is the basis of all industry, there will be keen competition for
it a competition becoming keener year by year as the competitors
multiply and wealth increases, the result of which competition will be
that the man of average means and capacity will have to give the very
highest price for the land that he will consent to give, rather than
go without it, and this highest price will be determined, not by the
amount that it takes out of his pocket, but by the amount it leaves
behind.
Here, for instance, are three farms of differing fertility estimated
to yield to the customary system of farming, 200, 300, and 400 net
profit respectively. Then, if the first of these fetches, after a
pretty close competition, 100 a year, this shows that no bidder will
give more than will leave him 100 to himself, but that the competition
of the others will not allow him to retain more ; in other words, that
100 is the lowest he will consent to keep, and the highest he will be
allowed to keep, so that 100 a year is the average profit of farming
amongst farmers of that class and means. But since he cannot hope to
keep more than 100, it does not matter to him what the surplus may be
which he is compelled to give up to his landlord; consequently the
other two farms will fetch respectively 200 and 300. Of course it is
the rate of profit, and not the actual profit of which we are speaking
of. The 100 is only quoted as an example. Amongst one class of farmers
the reserve will be higher, among another lower, according to their
means and the magnitude of their operations.
This is the theory, and it corresponds exactly with the facts; for
whether a farmer settles here or there, near a market or far-off,
whether he pays 100 a year for an indifferent farm, 150 for a better,
or 200 for a better still, he finds that except by some lucky accident
his profits as a farmer remain much the same ; which shows that his
rent is determined, not by what be has to pay away, but by what he is
determined to keep ; and this amount, this rate of profit, will, for
reasons already given, determine the rats of profit in all the
secondary industries, though they have no visible connection with the
land at all.
To put it compactly, the profits of industry all around are
determined by the rent of land. That amount of profit which the worker
on the land can save from his landlord will be all that the worker at
any industry can hope to get, and it will represent that minimum
margin to which he will consent to be beaten down rather than go
without the land.
What is the minimum margin?
The applicant for the land has a certain amount of capital (otherwise
he could not be an applicant), and for this he knows he could get
interest, and he also has the capacity to work. Consequently, the
least he will determine to keep will be what he could earn as a
labourer, plus the interest he could get on his capital. Actually
(except in the case of the poorest competitors for the smallest and
worst farms) it will be something rather more than this, for his
capital, such as it is, gives him a certain advantage in the position.
He and his competitors being none of them in danger of immediate want,
and therefore not pressed by necessity, will have a tendency to hold
back in the bidding when it begins to run high, and to cling to
something more than the closeness of the competition might seem to
demand ; and the larger his capital the greater will be his advantage,
not only because of his greater power and stronger inclination to hold
out for better terms, but also because the men of sufficient means to
require a large farm, such as he wants, are fewer in number, and the
competition in every way less keen and forced. Hence the smallest and
worst farms are always the highest rented, which is only another way
of saying that the profits on them are smallest.
Still, be the farms large or small, competition will always force
rents up, and therefore profits down to the smallest return the
average applicant of his class will consent to accept rather than go
without the land.
Land, as we have said, is the basis of all industry, and agriculture
is the fundamental industry.
Everyone recognises this; and in view of the hard struggle and
hand-to-mouth existence of the farmer, all sorts of projects are
proposed to ameliorate his lot.
One party advocates protection, another the lightening and equalising
of taxation, another cheapness of labour by assisted immigration
(making the labourer the scapegoat), another pins its faith on
railways, and so on.
Of these proposals some are good, some bad; but their effects
whichever way they tend, will not, except for the moment, affect the
farmers' profit one way or the other.
Let us suppose protection to be the true policy, and raising the
price of some particular article by a duty, say meat, see what the
result would be.
The rise of price in meat will produce two opposite effects. It will
immediately injure one class of farmers and benefit another. Those who
by reason of distance from market, unsuitability of their land for
grazing, or its still greater suitability for something else, do not
fatten stock, notwithstanding the rise in price (and these will be a
very large number), will suffer a distinct appreciable loss in
increased household expenses and increased cost of feeding their men,
without any advantage to set off; while those on the other hand, with
land specially adapted for grazing, who already made a profit by it
will make a larger profit still; and those on land passably suited for
it, who formerly made their profit by something else, may, perhaps,
change their system, and make their profit by grazing instead of by
those other things.
But the point is, that after the first start neither those who gain
nor those who lose will be any the better or the worse off, for their
gain or loss, because at the first renewal of their lease they will
transfer the gain or loss to their landlords.
For so long as all the land of the country is in the hands of a
comparatively few, so that there are more farmers wanting farms than
there are farms for them to have, so long will competition force land
values up to their maximum, and rent will mean to the farmer the
utmost that he can see his way to giving for the land rather than go
without it and let another take his place.
But for the very reason that competition is thus already at its full
stretch, it cannot be stretched any farther, and those farmers whose
narrow margin of profit is trenched on by their increased expenses
consequent on the rise in meat will insist on having that margin
restored, and they will be able to carry their point; for they were
already giving full value for their farms, and their farms (since they
produce no more and yet cost more to work) are now worth less, less
not only to the present occupants, but to any one else who might want
to take their place; therefore, the landlords cannot play off one
against another, and so must accept reduction.
Conversely, where the profits on land, already profitable for
grazing, have been increased by the duty, those lands will have become
just so much more valuable and will fetch so much more rent.
So, if you made a railway to every farmer's door you would simply
make the land more valuable. Compare those districts that have
railways with those that have none. In the former you will see a
greater population : probably, more cultivation, certainly higher
rents, but no higher farm profits; for where the carcass is there will
the eagles be gathered together; where returns are high, thither will
competitors flock. There may be no actual bidding against each other
among the applicants, but this is only because the landlord will
kindly take that trouble off their hands. He will put up the rent as
high as he thinks he can, too high at first perhaps if so his vacant
farm will soon cause him to correct his error, but whatever the
process, the result will be the same.
So, if by assisted immigration, you reduce the cost of labour by
half, or if by mechanical inventions you enable the farmer to do with
half the number of men (which would come to much the same thing to
him) you would be simply reducing the cost of working the land, and so
increasing the return to be got out of the land, and so increasing the
value of land, and so raising rents.
One after another labour-saving appliances have been introduced
within the last 20 years ; double-furrow ploughs, reapers and binders,
horse rakes, steam threshers, without improving the condition of the
farmer in the least. Never have there been so many aids and appliances
to industry as there are now, and never has the struggle of the farmer
been more severe.
So if you lightened taxation, or even abolished it altogether, it
would make no difference to the farmer, beyond the moment. At present
some leases stipulate that the landlord shall pay all rates; others
that the tenant shall pay them; others again that each shall pay half,
but it is all a mere adjustment of rent. The more taxes the less rent,
and vice versa.
If the farmer pays more rent it is because he has to pay less taxes,
and whether this is owing to the landlord paying them, or to there
being none to pay, makes not the least difference to the farmer.
So if nature herself instead of the mere instruments of production
were improved ; if the soil were suddenly doubled in fertility; if the
sun could be got to shine and the rain to fall exactly when and where
it was wanted ; if all weeds and plagues were abolished, it would come
to the same thing, and for the same reasons.
The Press is continually preaching that the fault of things all lies
with the farmer. He should be more industrious or more provident, he
should know something about chemistry, he should buy the best
appliances, and use the most advanced methods. It is very good advice
in its way perhaps, but it does not touch the question in the least.
If you passed every farmer through a technical college, if by a
network of meteorological stations and commercial agencies you
supplied him every day with a forecast of the weather, and the state
of the markets, if you supplied him gratis with all the best
machinery, if you trained him in habits of industry and economy,
foresight and skill, till you made him as much superior to what he now
is as a steam thresher is superior to a flail, you would enormously
increase his efficiency no doubt, but you would not add one farthing
to his profits. The whole benefit would go as before to the landlord,
and for the same reasons. You would not have eased the pressure of
competition, but only have put it into the power of every competitor
to offer more. Still, as before, rent would mean the utmost the farmer
could be forced to bid for the land rather than go without it.
Granting that there are many things that swallow up much of the
surplus that would otherwise come to the farmer; heavy taxes,
injudicious laws, bad roads, scarce labour; all these matter nothing
(as a great writer says) so long as behind them stands something which
swallows all that is left. So long as that something stands waiting
with open mouth, abolishing any of these only leaves so much more for
it to swallow.
Some people shrink from these conclusions saying, "it is a hard
doctrine" (as if truths could be dodged by shrinking from them.)
Others say that the remedy is the fixing of a fair rent.
But what is meant by a fair rent?
If Brown objects to his present rent of 100, saying it is to6 high,
and should be reduced to 80, and yet Jones is standing by prepared to
give 100, why should the rent be reduced? Why should Jones be
forbidden to have what he is ready to give 100 for, in order that
Brown should have it for 80? It is fair neither to Jones nor to the
landlord whatever it may be to Brown.
What would Brown think if Jones objected to [pay the 5s. for his
wheat that he had agreed to pay, saying it ought to be reduced to 4s.,
when Smith is standing by ready to give 5s.?
In the open market a "fair price" has no meaning. Hudibras*
saying still holds good that f< The value of a thing is just as
much as it will bring."
There is a remedy for this evil, and a very simple one, but it is not
the fixing of a fair rent.
"But," it will be said, "all farmers are not tenants.
Many own the land they occupy." True ; but all that this proves
is, not that the preceding remarks are incorrect, but that there is a
certain class to whom they do not apply. For the present we will let
the exception go for what it is worth. What I shall undertake to show
by- and- bye is that it is worth nothing.
But we shall have to present one or two other considerations at some
length before we are prepared to deal fully with this. For the present
we will let it stand over, only remarking that in farming, tenants are
the rule, occupying owners the exception, and that the exceptions grow
steadily fewer year by year. Not only in Tasmania, but in all the
other colonies, in the United States, and wherever, in short, land is
recognised as absolute private property, the divorce between
occupation and ownership is proceeding apace, and the very institution
which was designed to secure to the producer the full fruits of his
labour is becoming the means by which he is compelled to surrender
them to another.
The Real Sufferer.
As the landlord by virtue of his monopoly of the land holds the
applicant for it at his mercy, so the applicant once in possession
holds the labourer at his mercy.
The competition was first for possession of the land, it is now for
employment on the land. The competition is in the one case open and
direct, in the other disguised and indirect.
Labourers do not usually underbid each other for employment as
tenants overbid each other for possession, but it comes to much the
same thing as if they did: The more numerous the labourers in
proportion to the work to be done the lower the wages, and vice versa.
If the landlords were to divide their land into as many pieces of
equal value as there were applicants for it, and were to offer these
pieces separately, there would be no competition to run rents up, and
the landlord would have to take what he could get for it a merely
nominal rent.
To make money by his monopoly he must keep up its character as a
monopoly ; that is, he must offer his land in a single block so to
speak, and so compel competition.
And just as the landlord forces rents up by offering his whole land
for one tenant's occupation, and so setting all to compete for the
privilege of being that one, so the occupier in his turn forces wages
down by employing as few labourers as he can, and so setting all to
compete for the privilege of being among those few.
The secret of his power over the labourer is the same as that of his
landlord over him. It is not in his capital as is generally supposed,
but in his getting possession of more laud than he can use by his own
personal labour, and preventing other people from using it by their
personal labour, except for his profit.
The landlord makes the occupier give him his money; the occupier
makes the labourer give him his work.
In so far as the occupier can keep his wage expenditure below the
general level by doing the same work with fewer men, or paying them
less wages, he can retain the savings to himself; but in so far as he
only succeeds in keeping down the general cost of labour, he is only
keeping down the recognised cost of working the land, and so
increasing the value of land, and so raising rent ; and the result of
his efforts (as a rule), is only to keep down the general level, for
all are playing the same game, and any saving effected by one is soon
copied by all, and absorbed in a general reduced cost of production,
increasing the value of land and raising rent.
The productiveness of any industry that is, the amount it adds to the
general wealth or to the material comforts and enjoyments of the
people is measured by the difference in value between the thing
produced and the materials used up in producing it.
Thus, if a carpenter in a day makes a door worth 1, using up 8s.
worth of timber and nails in the process, the result of his work has
been to convert 8s. worth of rough timber into 20s. worth of finished
product, exhibiting as the measure of its productiveness a net
increase of 12s. How this increase is distributed and applied whether,
being an independent artisan, the maker can keep it all to himself, or
whether, being a hired servant, he must be content with his day's pay,
leaving the surplus to his employer ; whether he receives his share in
advance or has to wait for it; whether he consumes it or saves it up
all these make no difference to the fact that the increase was 12s.
From which we can see that the maintenance of the labourer forms no
part of the real cost of production, but only of his share, as
distinguished from the employer's share, of the profit.
If he is working on his own account and not for an employer everyone
sees that all he gets for his work is profit, and his maintenance the
use (or one of the uses) to which he puts that profit, just as an
employer's maintenance is the use (or one of the uses) to which he
puts his profit.
Or if the labourer, working for an employer, chooses to fast till his
employer has realised the product and paid him out of that product the
wages agreed upon, again everyone will see that they are not cost but
profit; the labourer's share and the employer's share being the two
parts into which the total profit is divided.
But if instead of working for himself or waiting and fasting, he
arranges to receive in advance from his employer the value (or part of
it) of that profit which he would have made if he had been working for
himself, or the value of the wages he would have received out of the
product if he had waited and fasted, still what he receives remains
essentially the same, the profit and not the cost of the work. It is
only the time and the manner of his receiving it that is changed;
still, as before, the proposition holds good that wages (of which
maintenance forms a part) is something to be added to the employer's
profit, not set off against it, in the national account, and that to
reduce wages is not to increase the general profits of industry but
only to apportion a smaller part of it to the labourer who is worst
off and most in need of it, and so leave a larger part for the
employer, the landlord, or some other person who is generally better
off and less in need of it.
An industry that does no more than provide bare maintenance for a
single man from day to day is to that extent a productive industry, a
gain and not a loss, though it provide neither rent to a landlord nor
profit to an employer.
An industry that provides not only for a man but for a family is more
productive still, a greater gain still, notwithstanding that it
represents increased consumption.
One that not only provides bare maintenance but comforts and
enjoyments as well is a still greater good, and gain to the country, a
cause for rejoicing, not regret. And yet if labourers' maintenance and
wages are, as is generally thought, the cost and not the profit of
industry, all these earnings should be lamented as expense, and the
greater the productiveness of any such industry as we have supposed,
the greater the loss to the country. The proceeds of labour, generally
speaking, are divided amongst three people, the labourer, the
employer, and the landlord. No one reckons the landlord's or the
employer's maintenance as part of the cost of production, and yet they
persist in reckoning the labourer's as such. Relatively, to the
employer, it may be, but absolutely, to the country, it is not.
However, this is but a side issue, of small consequence to my main
purpose, so we will pass on.
The employer always has to wait for his share till the product is
realised, while the labourer generally, and the landlord some times,
receives his in advance; and the employer sometimes makes a
miscalculation and gives more to the landlord in rent or to the
labourer in wages than a due regard to his own profit would warrant ;
or the enterprise may miscarry, and there may be no increase to
divide, or to make good what he has advanced. But such miscalculations
and failures do not affect the general proposition that, taking
industry as a whole, wages, profits, and rent, are the three different
portions into which its proceeds are divided. And since, as we have
seen, the competition for possession of the land keeps profits down to
a minimum, either rent will be determined by wages, or wages by rent;
that is to say, the larger the share of the proceeds the labourer
gets, the less will there be left for the landlord, and vice versa;
but as the landlord owns the land, he is master of the situation, and
rent determines wages.
But to say that rent determines wages, is to say that rent devours
wages. The labourer gets so little because the landlord gets so much.
[NOTE. I have adopted the division into rent, wages, and
profits, instead of into rent, wages, and interest, because though
less scientifically accurate, it is sufficiently accurate for my
present purpose, and enables me to keep my subject within more
manageable limits.]
Kent devours wages.
Suppose the labourer to ask for a rise and the farmer to refuse, on
the ground that he cannot afford it.
But presently something happens. A railway is made or a mine opened
in the neighbourhood, or some improved process enables a greater yield
to be obtained at the same cost, and there is now an appreciable
surplus. The labourer comes forward again and says, "You can
afford it now."
"Unfortunately, no," replies his employer. "I might
have done so, but my lease is nearly up, and these advantages you
refer to having made the land more valuable, my landlord has notified
that he means to raise the rent; and as there certainly is a greater
surplus available for rent than there was, I must give it, for if I
don't someone else will ; and so, as far as I am concerned, the
surplus you calculate upon has vanished."
In short, whenever there is an increase in the productiveness of
industry creating an additional surplus, and the labourer stretches
forth his hand for a share of it, the landlord pushes him aside, and
takes it all himself ; but as he keeps well out of sight in doing so,
using the employer as his instrument, his action is not perceived. And
as it is in the present so it has been in the past. Inventions and
discoveries have within the last century doubled the productiveness of
industry over and over again, but the labourer has no more benefited
by them than the employer has. The increase has been enormous, but, in
the primary industries at any rate, the landlord has taken it all.
But some will say, "The labourer's exertion is a fixed quantity.
The increased productiveness of his industry is in no degree due to
himself, but to the improved appliances he works with, and, that being
so, the person who supplies these appliances that is, the employer has
a right to the increase.
There is enough prima facie appearance of reason in this to have made
it worth discussing if the employer really got it, but he does not. He
gets interest, no doubt, on the additional expense he has incurred in
procuring the appliance, but he gets none of the increase of wealth
due to the increased efficiency of labour when aided by the appliance,
(once the appliance has come into general use); that, as we have seen,
goes to increase the value of land and raise rents, and while the
employer does not gain, the labourer in most cases actually loses; for
the usual result of labour-saving inventions, in the primary
industries at any rate, is not that the employer retains the same
hands to do more work, but that he discharges some of his men and does
the old amount of work with fewer hands.
It is the landlord, who has neither invented, nor supplied, nor put
to use the appliances, who gets the whole benefit of them.
To see that it is rent that devours wages, look at it another way.
Suppose the labourers demanding an increase and being refused, were
to say "Well, in six months we shall strike, so look out;
meanwhile we shall prepare for the struggle." So they save money,
subscribe funds, and organise; and at the time appointed present
themselves, provisioned and prepared.
What would happen?
Would the farmers refuse, and so all industry cease, or would they
consent to pay more than they could afford and go bankrupt?
Neither of these things would happen. The farmers would simply turn
to their landlords and say, "You see how it is. We cannot afford
higher wages, and the labourers won't work without them. Accept a
reduced rent, or we throw our farms on your hands."
What could the landlords do? Their rents are determined by
competition, and here is competition suddenly come to a stop. They
must make the best of the situation, and accept the reduction.
And so industry would go on as before, and the farmers make the same
profit as before. All that would have happened is that labour would
have gained a march upon monopoly and the labourer have wrested from
the landlord part of the blackmail he was accustomed to pay.
For it is the labourer from whom it is wrung. It is by keeping down
wages that the landlord thrives. The employer is merely the
instrument, who, for a consideration cut down by competition to the
lowest figure, undertakes all the trouble, the risk, and the odium of
the squeezing.
The price of labour, like the price of everything else, is determined
by supply and demand, and it is said that if employment is scarce it
is because there is not profitable employment on the land for all. Ah!
but profitable for whom? For the labourers, for the country, or for
one or two privileged people?
Here is a farm, selected from the assessment roll of this district as
a fair sample of a so-called agricultural farm consisting of 640 acres
and rented at 150. It keeps, I believe, at the outside, two men at
work the year round ; any other applicants for employment being
dismissed with the formula, "No work for you."
Two men to a whole square mile! And this on a farm within 15 miles of
the port of Hobart, and containing hardly an acre unfit for
cultivation.
All the produce that comes off this farm has to be raised by the
labour of these two men. and must realise over and above their wages
and keep and all collateral working expenses, a surplus of rent, 150;
rates and taxes, 20; employer's profit (say), 100; total 270; being a
profit of 135 to each man. No man, in short, is allowed the
opportunity to earn a living on this square mile of cultivable land
unless he produces, over and above the supply of his own modest wants,
a net annual surplus of 135 to hand over to somebody else.
If employment is restricted, it is land monopoly that restricts it.
It is not that there is not abundance of land to use, abundance of
use to put it to, and abundance of profit to be made from it, but that
the tendency of monopoly is to keep hungry mouths off rather than to
take willing hands on. It is naturally concerned only to get as big a
share as possible to itself, and is not concerned whether other people
have a chance to get a share or not.
The occupier will not engage more men than he can help.
But suppose his hand is forced.
Suppose the Trade Unions were to change their tactics (as they may do
any day), and instead of trying to restrict the field of employment
were to undertake to extend it. Suppose a Trade Union of farm
labourers were to say to the farmer, "You have been accustomed to
employ two men only on this farm. Well, not a man shall take service
with you unless you undertake to engage four, and at the same wages."
Does anybody doubt that the two extra men could produce more than
they consume and use up, and so be productively employed ? And if the
net surplus to hand over to the landlord were less, why he would have
to take less.
The earnings of the two extra men, reckoning their wages and keep
only, would be 100 a year, and if that left a surplus of 20 less for
the landlord, there would still be 80 to the good. For, as I have
elsewhere pointed out, the labourer's maintenance (much more his whole
earnings), so long as he replaces what he receives, is not cost of
production but profit; the labourer's share of it. If an industry does
nothing more than maintain one man continuously it is to that extent
productive.
But the landlord's position is too strong for him to stand in much
fear of such combinations as these, and the whole tendency of affairs
is to increase his power.
The landlords as a class get more, without the least exertion,
outlay, or risk, out of the labour of the community than they could if
the whole working community were their slaves.
|