How I Came to Embrace the Principles
Embraced by Henry George
Gavin Putland
[Reprinted from Progress, 2000 (estimated)]
Science tells us that we are genetically programmed to maximize our
chances of passing on our genes. Rigid observance of the Ten
Commandments is not a likely output of this program. Neither is loving
one's neighbour as oneself. But selfishness, possessiveness, jealousy,
hatred, xenophobia, territorialism, treachery, homicide, genocide,
adultery, larceny, slander, deceit and dissimulation are all likely
outputs; and this prediction is confirmed by history and current
events.
Like science and history, Christianity teaches that we all have an
inherited inclination toward evil. And as reason tells us that an
inclination to sin does not become an evolutionary advantage until one
actually commits the sin, so Christianity teaches that man's descent
into evil began with a single act.
In this Darwinian struggle, the strongest and most unscrupulous
individuals build social systems that make them still stronger, hence
better able to build systems, and so on. Consequently some of our most
cherished institutions are, in the terminology of the liberation
theologians of Latin America, merely ``structures of sin''. These
structures cause difficulties which are sources of individual
temptation, completing a vicious cycle: individual sin and
institutional sin are inseparable.
The foregoing logic is almost universally ignored. Political radicals
emphasize institutional sin but don't seem to believe in the
universality of individual sin; for them, structures of sin are the
work of a particular socio-economic class (e.g. capitalists or
landowners) while the rest of us are innocent victims. Christians, to
the contrary, are wary of individual sin but seem oblivious to the
sinfulness of socio-economic institutions; in particular, the criteria
by which seemingly devout Christians choose their careers and their
marriage partners are almost identical to those of society at large.
Hence this writer, who is a political radical AND a Christian, finds
himself an outcast among outcasts twice over: an outcast among
Christians for his anti-Establishment views, and an outcast among
political radicals for believing that old superstition about Original
Sin.
I was born in Home Hill (north Queensland) in 1963, the eldest son of
a non-smoking teetotalling Methodist schoolteacher. I was just like
the old man only more so: Dux of Ipswich Grammar for 1980, a Medallist
of the University of Queensland for 1984, and a PhD (electrical
engineering) in 1996. But my professional life, both before and after
my postgraduate years, was singularly undistinguished. So what went "wrong"?
From 1985 to 1988 the major distraction was religion. I was troubled
by the claims of Roman Catholicism and might have fallen for them had
I not discovered the counter-claims of Eastern Orthodoxy, which I
found so convincing that I was received into the Orthodox Church in
1988. This of course is not the usual mode of conversion. The usual
mode is to marry a Greek, and is much to be preferred. To convert
purely out of conviction is to be a renegade to the old flock and an
odd-ball to the new.
The other distraction was political economy. In about 1983, while
still an undergraduate, I formed the opinion that land speculation was
immoral because if some people got something for nothing, others must
get nothing for something. Moreover the winners were those who could
buy and sell when it suited them while the losers were those who could
not; and the ability to buy and sell when it was profitable, rather
than when it was unavoidable, came from being better off in the first
place.
So my initial view of the land problem was based solely on equity,
and the only remedy I could suggest was the usual social-democratic
blunt instrument: a capital gains tax. But equity was a two-way
street: if it was unfair to pocket unearned increases in land values,
it was also unfair to suffer uncompensated losses. Therefore, I
concluded, landowners should be compensated for devaluations caused by
planning decisions. That was the remedy for NIMBYism.
In 1997, when I was an academic spending too much time on
administration, I formed my first independent idea on unemployment: "Making
work destroys jobs." That is, compliance costs divert resources
from productive uses to unproductive uses, reducing the national
capacity to pay wages.
Later that year I realized that income tests and assets tests on
welfare are equivalent to income taxes and wealth taxes payable by
welfare recipients. Means tests don't reduce the tax burden, because
they ARE TAXES. It is therefore perfectly inane to ask whether we can
"afford" to abolish means tests, because any resulting "tax
increase" merely substitutes an honest tax for a dishonest one.
Moreover, when we count means tests as taxes, we see that the heaviest
tax burden is placed on the transition from welfare to work. To the
extent that the burden is shifted onto employers by the wage-fixing
process, it discourages hiring.
On the strength of these insights, I quit my precarious academic job
and wrote the book SIX MONTHS TO FULL EMPLOYMENT (November 1998), in
which I reinvented the "basic income" approach to full
employment policy. (Georgists may prefer the term "citizen's
dividend" to "basic income".) My basic income was
perfectly Dry, without means tests or activity tests. For want of
interest from publishers, I eventually placed the book in the public
domain. (It is still available on my WWW site, but should not always
be taken as an expression of my current views. For example, I no
longer object to activity tests per se, but I caution against narrow
definitions of "activity".)
My entry in the Tax Reform Challenge of March 1998, as suggested by
its title "Fourteen Steps to Full Employment", was a short
preview of the book. The "Challenge" was to rebut a
submission which argued for 100 percent site rental collection
implemented in stages. In response, I reinvented a form of the (John
Stuart) Mill tax, which appropriated FUTURE increments in land values.
I didn't know it was Mill's idea. Instead I took my hint from Phil
Day's book, LAND (Brisbane: Australian Academic Press, 1995). Whereas
Day [p.69, n.1] said that taxes should be adjusted in response to
non-zero sale prices, I said they should be adjusted in response to
deviations in sale prices from the base-date valuations. (Note the
implication: the administrative machinery for a Mill tax is identical
to that for full site rental collection.) The main advantages of this
system, as I saw it, were that speculation would end and that
landowners would be automatically compensated for devaluations.
In my Challenge entry, land speculation was only loosely related to
unemployment. "Land speculation is a cumulative and uncompensated
impost on the cost of living," I wrote -- the implication being
that land prices caused upward pressure on labour costs, whereas my
main strategy was to reduce labour costs by turning the dole into a
wage subsidy. I understood that land speculation, like red tape,
represented a diversion of resources from productive to unproductive
uses. But I naively imagined land rents being shifted into prices,
failed to relate land speculation to the natural rate of unemployment,
and had no notion of "all-devouring rent". So it is not
surprising that my book eventually included only one sentence on land
value taxation, citing George's PROGRESS AND POVERTY and THE CONDITION
OF LABOR in support of its economic advantages, and citing my
Challenge entry as a solution to the attendant political difficulties.
Neither is it surprising that I do not clearly remember where I first
saw the name of Henry George. Maybe it was in Heilbroner's THE WORLDLY
PHILOSOPHERS, where a passage on land speculation from P&P is
quoted. I remembered the quote but not the name. And maybe it was on
my first reading of Phil Day's LAND that I was pulled up by the
endnote accusing Heilbroner of "tabloid journalism" [p.108,
n.4]. In any case, the clash between Day and Heilbroner directed my
attention to P&P, which says (Bk III, ch.2):
As Produce = Rent + Wages + Interest,
Therefore, Produce - Rent = Wages + Interest.
As competition limits Wages and Interest to their marginal values,
Rent takes the rest. Thus, for the first time in history, the laws of
Rent, Wages and Interest were brought into harmony: George was to
economics as Copernicus was to astronomy. And he had exposed the
biggest single "structure of sin".
But I disagreed with George's dismissal of Mill. A Mill tax would
remove the speculative component of Rent, causing Wages + Interest to
rise. And such is the rate of increase in land values that if a Mill
tax had been implemented in George's day, it would now be collecting
close to 100 percent of the gross Rent. So I remained a Millist.
Then on Saturday, 20 February 1999, I wrote in an email message:
How does one make a 100% land rental ``tax'' politically
acceptable? By dressing it up as a means test... How does one make a
non-means-tested Universal Basic Income politically acceptable? By
combining it with the said land rental tax in a single statement...
[see PROGRESS, May/June 1999, pp.12-13; cf. The Single Means Test.
Thus began an interesting week. On the Wednesday, having given up
hope of finding a publisher for my book on the causes and remedies
of unemployment, I declared myself unemployed. On the Friday night,
as I walked home from the bus stop after a Bible study meeting, it
struck me that if all productivity taxes were abolished, the benefit
would appear as increased Rent and increased capitalized land
values. Hence, if the lost public revenue were replaced by land
taxes, the sum of capitalized land values would return to its former
value, just as it would under a Mill tax [see PROGRESS, Sep./Oct.
1999, pp.8-9]. In other words, introduction of a Mill tax followed
by abolition of productivity taxes would preserve public revenue at
its present level. Mill could have been a Single Taxer, George could
have been a Millist, and I had seen the cat while walking up
Daffodil Crescent in the dark.
After the Liturgy of Saturday, 27 February, I told my story to a
fellow parishioner (who presumably didn't understand it) and
concluded, "I was an Orthodox Georgist for a week. Now I'm an
heretical Georgist!"
My position is "heretical" because it implies that H.G.
didn't quite see the cat. In P&P (Bk VI, ch.1), he stated
explicitly that the benefit of tax cuts from greater economy in
government would accrue to landowners. The words "from greater
economy in government" can be omitted without affecting the
logic. If productivity taxes were cut in order to clear the way for
a heavy land tax, the benefit of those tax cuts would also accrue to
landowners as an increase in gross Rent. If that increase were
reclaimed by a Mill tax, the after-tax rental value of land (hence
its capitalized value) and the total public revenue would be roughly
as before ("roughly" because we need to subtract the
speculative premium and add the growth dividend).
George didn't draw this conclusion. Nor did he acknowledge that a
Mill tax is sufficient to end speculation. In P&P; (Bk VII,
ch.3) George wrote "All that can be said of this [Mill's] plan
is, that it might be better than nothing." In THE SCIENCE OF
POLITICAL ECONOMY (Bk II, ch.7), he hardened his position, saying
that Mill's proposition "amounted to nothing whatever, as
landlords were ready to sell land for what would give them any
unearned increment not yet in sight" -- a response that
envisages a buyback scheme rather than an incremental tax scheme,
and which fails to allow for the heavy discounting rates applied to
capitalization of (uncertain) future increments in Rent.
Geoists are not noted for unity at the best of times. As the
undersigned geoist is overtly religious, backs Mill against George,
packages geoism as more of a welfare reform than a tax reform, and
(most recently) advocates alliances with lesser rent-takers in order
to defeat the land power, he is condemned to be more isolated than
most.
|