.


SCI LIBRARY

The Essential Reform:
Land Value Taxation
In Theory & Practice

C. H. Chomley & R. L. Outhwaite


[Originally published in 1909 by Sidgwick & Jackson, Ltd.,
London -- Part 1 of 15]


The aim of the following pages being to discuss a system of taxation in all its bearings, it will be necessary to consider for a little the principles upon which taxation is or may be founded, in order that we may decide what system appears to be most in accord with justice. The most just, it may be confidently asserted, will in the long run prove to be the most expedient and socially useful, whatever the initial difficulties in the way of its adoption. In making justice the touchstone of political proposals we stand on firm ground, for while men will honestly form a hundred different opinions as to the social, political, and economic effects of any course of action, there is comparative unanimity among unprejudiced minds as to what constitutes justice, and history may be searched in vain for an instance when just conduct on the part of a man or a nation has resulted in evil.

The canon of taxation which has the greatest weight of orthodox authority behind it is that every citizen should contribute to the needs of the State in proportion to his ability so to do. There is a plausibility about this which causes it to be generally regarded as indisputable and indeed self-evident. Taxation is postulated as an evil -- a necessary evil, no doubt - but a bad thing in itself nevertheless; and since it is granted that the State must have funds to carry out its functions, it seems logically to follow that all citizens should contribute to those funds in proportion to their means. But in this argument there is involved an assumption, which we hope to prove unwarranted -- namely, that the State, representing the community, has no funds or has insufficient funds of its own to meet demands upon it, and is therefore obliged to take a portion of the property belonging to its citizens.

If we can show that, on the contrary, the community is the rightful owner of property the returns from which would be sufficient to pay for exercise of all its reasonable activities, it follows that there is no justification for infringing the property rights of individuals, and that the maxim, "Make each pay according to his capacity," is much akin to the injunction of a brigand captain to band, "Rob the rich and spare the poor."

The only difference between humane brigandage and taxation of the people according to their ability to pay is, that the latter is sanctioned by law and assumption that the taking of private property the only means of meeting public needs; but on these lines taxation is nevertheless an infringement of the rights of private property, which the advocates of such taxation profess to hold sacred.

Not only is the principle of payment according to ability far from perfect, but in existing systems of taxation it is only half-heartedly put into practice. The income tax, which is supposed to be founded on this principle, takes as much from the man with a large family to keep as from the bachelor with no dependents, though it is manifest that their abilities to meet the impost are very far from equal. To property taxes the same criticism applies, and they are open to the further objection that the property of the poor man consists for the most part of material things, such as houses, furniture, stock and implements, which cannot be hidden from the revenue officer, while the property of the rich is largely invisible or easily concealed. Stocks and shares can be transferred temporarily from the country, they can be under-valued; costly jewelry can be hidden. There are, in fact, so many means by which the wealthy can evade a tax on property that it has been abandoned by most of the countries which have experimented with it.

But while lip service is accorded to the canon of taxation discussed above, another canon which finds no favour with political economists is acted upon throughout the world to such an extent that in accordance with it the greater part of the world's public revenues are raised. This canon is, "Tax a man upon what he consumes," or, in other words, "Tax him according to his needs." This is the basis of all tariffs. The more clothes, the more food, the more drink or tobacco a man requires, the more he must pay. Morally, such taxes are indefensible. They take away private property, as do the income tax and the property tax; but, unlike these imposts, customs and import duties make no attempt at proportioning revenue burdens to the tax-payer's means of meeting them. They fall principally on the poor, for it is articles of general consumption, such as tea and sugar, which yield the most revenue, because they are necessities to the masses of the population, who can least afford to pay taxes. While all of them are vicious in principle, customs and excise duties vary in unfairness and hurtfulness according to the methods by which they are levied, and the articles upon which they are imposed. Revenue duties, such as those upon tea and other articles not produced in the country which taxes them, are economical because the full amount of the tax paid goes into the coffers of the State. Protective duties -- that is to say, duties levied upon goods imported into a country and not upon similar goods produced within its borders -- are, on the contrary, wasteful, because in addition to the money taken out of the pockets of the consumers of the imported article in the form of duty, which goes into the public revenue, much more money is taken from the consumers of similar home-made articles in the shape of higher prices to the manufacturer, who is enabled by the import duty to charge more than he could do if he were unsheltered from the competition of dutiable goods from abroad. On the other hand, certain special disadvantages are involved in fixed revenue duties, such as those upon tea and tobacco -- fixed duties levied according to number or quantity and not according to value upon articles of every kind. The tea duty, for instance, of 4d. per lb. amounts to a tax of 33-1/3 per cent. on the poor man's expenditure of ls. upon a pound of cheap tea, and lets off his wealthier neighbour who buys tea at 2s. per lb with a tax of less than 17 per cent. on his outlay. Similarly, cigars being subject to a fixed duty of 6s per lb. irrespective of quality, the man of small means who buys a 3d. cigar smokes only 1d. worth of tobacco with 2d. worth of tax, and the man of large means, in his cigar at a shilling, smokes only 2d. worth of tax with 10d. worth of tobacco. In every shilling expended the poor man is paying just four times as much tax as the rich.

From every point of view, therefore, customs and excise duties are unfair and burdensome to the poorer classes; their great recommendation to Chancellors of the Exchequer is that their grossness and effect are concealed from those who pay them. Prices rise when duties are imposed; the purchaser grumbles, perhaps, at the rise in price, but in ninety-nine cases out of a hundred fails to see how he is being fleeced.

The foregoing strictures upon customs and excise duties are concerned with them only as instruments for raising revenue. They have other aspects. Taxes upon alcohol and tobacco, for instance, are approved of by certain people as a means for restricting the consumption of these articles. Protective duties meet with approval from others on the assumption that they encourage home production. This assumption we do not grant, but, even if it were justified, no case for such duties from the standpoint of revenue would be made out, since it is obvious that the more successful they are in checking imports and thereby increasing local production, the less effective will they be in contributing to the Treasury. As to the moral effects of duties upon alcohol, they are at least questionable, and in so far as they check drinking they fail in their function as revenue-producing taxes.

Before going on to set out what we believe to be the true principle of taxation it will be useful to glance at one or two other taxes which can lay no claim to be founded on any principle but that of grabbing, where grabbing is comparatively cheap and easy. Such is the inhabited house duty, a peculiarly noxious tax on a special form of property with a direct tendency to check the building of houses, and therefore to promote high rents and overcrowding. Stamp duties of various kinds are a levy upon the business activities of the people, taking from them without return or justification (always providing that the justification of necessity does not exist) a portion of their earnings. Various duties on the property of deceased persons passing on their death to others are a form of which inflict less hardship, perhaps, than other taxes, but have no raison-d'etre except a doubtful application of the principle of levying taxation in accordance with ability to pay -- we say doubtful application because, while it is true that duties on large properties are levied at a higher rate than upon small ones, it is nevertheless true that among the beneficiaries of an estate, who are the real payers of the tax, one might be very rich and another very poor, yet suffer equal reductions of their legacies for the benefit of the Exchequer.

The other principal sources of revenue in the United Kingdom are the post-office and licences of various kinds. When the receipts from posts and telegraphs arc in excess of the cost of operating them, the surplus is a tax with nothing to justify it but the fact that it takes the place pro tanto of perhaps more objectionable forms of taxation. When the revenue equals the expenditure, the receipts are not the proceeds of taxation but are merely payment for services rendered.

Licences vary considerably in their nature and the principle upon which they are based. Some, such as those imposed on the followers of several trades and occupations in which there is no monopoly, are demanded partly to pay the cost of super'4sing the conduct of the licensee in the supposed interest of the public, and in greater part as a means of obtaining revenue at the expense of the licensee or those who employ him. Licences to sell liquor stand upon a different footing. Rightly or wrongly the State has established a monopoly in the liquor-selling business in business; this monopoly is the property of the people as a whole and has great value. While it exists the licensed traders, who pay for the right to sell liquor, are not, in fact, being taxed at all. They get full value for their money, and under present conditions in this country many of the traders, whose licence fees are absurdly low, are receiving from the community a large annual gift in the difference between the great value of the partial immunity from competition which they enjoy and the small amount they pay pay for this immunity.

We have now glanced at most existent forms of taxation, and have found that none of them are or can ever truly be in accord with the much-lauded principle of payment proportionate to the tax-payer's ability. We have also endeavoured to show that this principle, even if enforcible, would do nothing to justify the taxation which it is intended to regulate, and is at best a statement of the most considerate method of robbing individuals of their property in order to fill the coffers of the State. We have pointed out that the only justification for this robbery -- or, if the word robbery be objected to, for this forcible taking of private property - rests in an assumption of its necessity following another assumption that the State has rightfully no property of its own.

Let us now see whether these assumptions are justified, whether there is not on the contrary a fund rightfully belonging to the community which would defray all the expenses of the State, and consequently by its appropriation remove the need of taking form individuals property belonging to them. If such a fund exists it follows that appropriation of it by its rightful owner, the community, is not taxation in the sense that word usually conveys; it is not a more or less arbitrary levy on private property for purblic purposes. The fund to which we refer is the land value created by society, and when the State taxes this value it will be on the road to the abolition of all burdensome taxes and the establishment of economic justice.

Proposals to tax land values are always and everywhere strenuously resisted by those in possession of them, who regard as sacred a form of property which enriches them without effort on their own part and lays the work of the world under tribute. The landowners have long been a privileged class holding an undue proportion of wealth influence and power in the country, able thereby to remove most of the public burdens from their own to other shoulders and they fiercely resent any attempt to make them pay for the privileges they enjoy, by taxing the value of the land they hold. Such a tax forms the subject of this volume, in which an endeavour will be made to show that it is the most just and consequently the most socially useful of all taxes, as indeed it incontrovertibly must be, if the community and not the individual has created the value of the land.

Its justice and usefulness we bbelieve capable of convincing proof as a mere fiscal reform even to those who hesitate to assent to the proposition that private property in land and kindred monopolies is indefensible.

The canon by which we hold that the claims to justice of any tax should be judged and in the light of which its amount should be regulated may be phrased in the following words: Every person should contribute to the expenses of the State in proportion to the privileges conferred on him by the community of which the State is the representative." The application of this canon to the taxation of land values, and the nature and meaning of land values considered from several points of view, will form the subject of the next chapter.


Part 1 * Part 2 * Part 3 * Part 4 * Part 5
Part 6 * Part 7 * Part 8 * Part 9 * Part 10
Part 11 * Part 12 * Part 13 * Part 14 * Part 15